ordinal arithmetic: Information and Much More from Answers.com
In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an explicit well-ordered set which represents the operation or by using transfinite recursion. Cantor normal form provides a standardized way of writing ordinals. The so-called "natural" arithmetical operations retain commutativity at the expense of continuity.
Addition
The union of two disjoint well-ordered sets S and T can be well-ordered. The order-type of that union is the
ordinal which results from adding the order-types of S and T. If two well-ordered sets are not already disjoint,
then they can be replaced by order-isomorphic disjoint sets, e.g. replace S by S×{0} and T by T×{1}.
Thus the well-ordered set S is written "to the left" of the well-ordered set T, meaning one defines an order on
S T in which
every element of S is smaller than every element of T. The sets S and T themselves keep the ordering
they already have. This addition is associative and generalizes the addition of natural
numbers.
The first transfinite ordinal is ω, the set of all natural numbers. Let's try to visualize the ordinal ω+ω: two copies of the natural numbers ordered in the normal fashion and the second copy completely to the right of the first. If we write the second copy as {0'<1'<2',...} then ω+ω looks like
- 0 < 1 < 2 < 3 < ... < 0' < 1' < 2' < ...
This is different from ω because in ω only 0 does not have a direct predecessor while in ω+ω the two elements 0 and 0' do not have direct predecessors. Here are 3 + ω and ω + 3:
- 0 < 1 < 2 < 0' < 1' < 2' < ...
- 0 < 1 < 2 < ... < 0' < 1' < 2'
After relabeling, the former just looks like ω itself while the latter does not: we have 3 + ω = ω. But ω + 3 is not equal to ω since the former has a largest element and the latter does not. So our addition is not commutative.
One can see for example that (ω + 4) + ω = ω + (4 + ω) = ω + ω.
The definition of addition can also be given inductively (the following induction is on β):
- α + 0 = α,
- α + (β+1) = (α+β)+1 (here, "+1" denotes the successor of an ordinal),
- and if δ is limit then α+δ is the limit of the α+β for all β<δ.
Using this definition, we also see that ω+3 is a successor ordinal (it is the successor of ω+2) whereas 3+ω is the limit of 3+0=3, 3+1=4, 3+2=5, etc., which is just ω.
Zero is an additive identity α + 0 = 0 + α = α.
Addition is associative (α + β) + γ = α + (β + γ).
Addition is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument:
but the analogous relation does not hold for the left argument; instead we only have:
Unrestricted subtraction cannot be defined for ordinals. However, there is a cancellation law from the left: If α + β = α + γ, then β = γ. On the other hand, cancellation from the right does not work:
- 3 + ω = 0 + ω = ω but 3≠0
Also if β ≤ α, then there is a unique γ such that α = β + γ.
Multiplication
The Cartesian product, S×T, of two well-ordered sets S and T can be well-ordered by a variant of lexicographical order which puts the least significant position first. Effectively, each element of T is replaced by a disjoint copy of S. The order-type of the Cartesian product is the ordinal which results from multiplying the order-types of S and T. Again, this operation is associative and generalizes the multiplication of natural numbers.
Here is ω·2:
- 00 < 10 < 20 < 30 < ... < 01 < 11 < 21 < 31 < ...
and we see: ω·2 = ω + ω. But 2·ω looks like this:
- 00 < 10 < 01 < 11 < 02 < 12 < 03 < 13 < ...
and after relabeling, this looks just like ω and so we get 2·ω = ω ≠ ω·2. Hence multiplication of ordinals is not commutative.
Distributivity partially holds for ordinal arithmetic: R(S+T) = RS + RT. However, the other distributive law (T+U)R = TR + UR is not generally true: (1 + 1) ·ω = 2·ω = ω while 1·ω + 1·ω = ω+ω which is different. Therefore, the ordinal numbers do not form a ring.
The definition of multiplication can also be given inductively (the following induction is on β):
- α · 0 = 0,
- α · (β+1) = (α·β)+α,
- and if δ is limit then α·δ is the limit of the α·β for all β<δ.
The main properties of the product are:
- α·0 = 0·α = 0.
- One is a multiplicative identity α·1 = 1·α = α.
- Multiplication is associative (α·β)·γ = α·(β·γ).
- Multiplication is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument:
- (α < β and γ > 0)
γ·α < γ·β,
- but if one reverses the arguments the inequality does not work:
- for example, 1 < 2 but 1·ω = 2·ω = ω.
- Instead one gets α ≤ β
α·γ ≤ β·γ.
- There is a cancellation law: If α > 0 and α · β = α · γ, then β = γ.
- The example above shows that cancellation from the right does not work.
- α·β = 0
α = 0 or β = 0.
- α· (β + γ) = α·β + α·γ (distributive law on the left). On the other hand, there is no distributive law on the right.
-
- e.g. (ω + 1) ·2 = ω + 1 + ω + 1 = ω + ω + 1 = ω·2 + 1 which is not ω·2 + 2.
Also for all α and β, if β > 0, then there are unique γ and δ such that α = β · γ + δ and δ < β (a kind of Euclidean division; this doesn't mean the ordinals are a Euclidean domain, however, since they aren't even a ring).
Exponentiation
Exponentiation of well ordered sets is defined as follows. If the exponent is a finite set, the power is the product of iterated multiplication. For instance, ω2 = ω·ω using the operation of ordinal multiplication.
To generalize this to the case when the exponent is an infinite ordinal requires a different viewpoint. Note that ω·ω can be visualized as the set of functions from 2 = {0,1} to ω = {0,1,2,...}, ordered lexicographically with the least significant position first:
- (0,0) < (1,0) < (2,0) < (3,0) < ... < (0,1) < (1,1) < (2,1) < (3,1) < ... < (0,2) < (1,2) < (2,2) < ...
Here for brevity, we have replaced the function {(0,k), (1,m)} by the ordered pair (k, m).
Similarly, for any finite exponent n, ωn can be visualized as the set of functions from n (the domain) to the natural numbers (the range). These functions can be abbreviated as n-tuples of natural numbers.
For ωω, we might try to visualize the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. However, if we try to use any effectively defined ordering on this set, we find it is not well-ordered. Using the variant lexicographical ordering again, we restrict the set of sequences to those for which only a finite number of elements of the sequence are different from zero. This is naturally motivated as the limit of the finite powers of the base (similar to the concept of coproduct in algebra).
The lexicographical order on this set is a well ordering that resembles the ordering of natural numbers written in decimal notation, except with digit positions reversed, and with arbitrary natural numbers instead of just the digits 0-9:
- (0,0,0,...) < (1,0,0,0,...) < (2,0,0,0,...) < ... <
- (0,1,0,0,0,...) < (1,1,0,0,0,...) < (2,1,0,0,0,...) < ... <
- (0,2,0,0,0,...) < (1,2,0,0,0,...) < (2,2,0,0,0,...)
- < ... <
- (0,0,1,0,0,0,...) < (1,0,1,0,0,0,...) < (2,0,1,0,0,0,...)
- < ...
In general, any well ordered set B can be raised to the power of another well ordered set E, resulting in another well ordered set, the power BE: each elements is a function from E to B such that only a finite number of elements of the domain E map to an element larger than the least element of the range B; the order is lexicographic with the least significant position first.
- We find 1ω = 1, 2ω = ω,
.
The order type of the power BE is the ordinal which results from applying ordinal exponentiation to the order type of the base B and the order type of the exponent E.
The definition of exponentiation can also be given inductively (the following induction is on β, the exponent):
- α0 = 1,
- αβ+1 = (αβ)·α, and
- if δ is limit, then αδ is the limit of the αβ for all β < δ.
Properties of ordinal exponentiation (shared by exponentiation of natural numbers since they are the finite ordinals):
- α0 = 1.
- If 0 < α, then 0α = 0.
- 1α = 1.
- α1 = α.
- αβ·αγ = αβ + γ.
- (αβ)γ = αβ·γ.
But there are α, β, and γ for which
- (α·β)γ ≠ αγ·βγ. For instance, (ω·2)2 = ω2·2 ≠ ω2·4.
Ordinal exponentiation is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument:
- If γ > 1 and α < β, then γα < γβ.
- If α < β, then αγ ≤ βγ. Note, for instance, that 2 < 3 and yet 2ω = 3ω = ω.
Although different bases raised to the same power may yield the same result, it is impossible to obtain the same ordinal by raising the same base to two different powers unless the base is 0 or 1. That is, if α > 1 and αβ = αγ, then β = γ.
For all α and β, if 1 < β ≤ α then there exist unique γ, δ, and ρ such that
- α = βγ · δ + ρ
such that 0 < δ < β and ρ < βγ.
Warning: Ordinal exponentiation is quite different from cardinal exponentiation. For example, the ordinal
exponentiation 2ω = ω, but the cardinal exponentiation is the cardinality of the continuum which is much larger than
. To avoid confusing ordinal exponentiation
with cardinal exponentiation, one can use symbols for ordinals (e.g. ω) in the former and symbols for cardinals (e.g.
) in the latter.
Cantor normal form
Ordinal numbers present a rich arithmetic. Every ordinal number α can be uniquely written as , where k is a natural number, c1,c2,...,ck are positive integers, and
β1 > β2 > ... > βk are ordinal numbers (we allow
βk = 0). This decomposition of α is called the Cantor normal form of
α, and can be considered the positional base-ω numeral system. The highest
exponent β1 is called the degree of α, and satisfies
. The equality
β1 = α applies if and only if α = ωα. In that
case Cantor normal form does not express the ordinal in terms of smaller ones; this can happen as explained below.
A minor variation of Cantor normal form, which is usually slightly easier to work with, is to set all the numbers
ci equal to 1 and allow the exponents to be equal. In other words, every ordinal number α can be
uniquely written as , where k is a natural number, and
are ordinal numbers.
The Cantor normal form allows us to uniquely express—and order—the ordinals α which are built from the natural numbers
by a finite number of arithmetical operations of addition, multiplication and “raising ω to the power of”: in other words,
assuming β1 < α in the Cantor normal form, we can also express the exponents
βi in Cantor normal form, and making the same assumption for the βi as for α and so on recursively, we get a system of notation for these ordinals (for
example, is one).
The set of finite arithmetical expressions of this form is called ε0 (epsilon
nought). It is the smallest ordinal that does not have a finite arithmetical expression, and the smallest ordinal such
that , i.e. in Cantor normal form the exponent is not smaller than the ordinal itself. It
is the limit of the sequence ω, ωω,
, etc. The ordinal ε0
is important for various reasons in arithmetic (essentially because it measures the proof-theoretic strength of the
first-order Peano arithmetic: that is, Peano's
axioms can show transfinite induction up to any ordinal less than ε0 but not up to ε0 itself).
The Cantor normal form also allows us to compute sums and products of ordinals: to compute the sum, for example, one needs
merely know that ωβc + ωβ'c' is ωβ'c' if β' > β (if β' = β one
can obviously rewrite this as ωβ(c + c'), and if β'
< β the expression is already in Cantor normal form); and to compute products, the essential fact is that when
is in Cantor normal form (and α>0) then
. Also
, if n is a non-zero natural
number.
To compare two ordinals written in Cantor normal form, first compare β1, then c1, then β2, then c2, etc.. At the first difference, the ordinal which has the larger component is the larger ordinal. If they are the same until one terminates before the other, then the one which terminates first is smaller.
Natural operations
The natural sum and natural product operations on ordinals were defined in 1906 by Gerhard Hessenberg, and are sometimes called the Hessenberg sum (or product). (Jacobsthal
defined a natural power operation in 1907, which is very rarely used.) They are also sometimes called the Conway operations, as they are just the addition and multiplication (restricted to ordinals) of
Conway's field of surreal numbers. They have
the advantage that they are associative and commutative, and natural product distributes over natural sum. The cost of making
these operations commutative is that they lose the continuity in the right argument which is a property of the ordinary sum and
product. The natural sum of α and β is sometimes denoted by α#β, and the natural product by a sort of doubled × sign. To define
the natural sum of two ordinals, consider once again the disjoint union ST of two well-ordered sets having these
order types. Start by putting a partial order on this disjoint union by taking the orders on S and T separately but
imposing no relation between S and T. Now consider the order types of all well-orders which extend this
partial order: the least upper bound of all these ordinals (which is, actually, not merely a least upper bound but actually a
greatest element) is the natural sum. Also, inductively, we can define the natural sum of α and β (by simultaneous
induction on α and β) as the smallest ordinal greater than the natural sum of α and γ for all
γ<β and of γ and β for all γ<α.
The natural sum is associative and commutative: it is always greater or equal to the usual sum, but it may be greater. For example, the natural sum of ω and 1 is ω+1 (the usual sum), but this is also the natural sum of 1 and ω.
To define the natural product of two ordinals, consider once again the cartesian product S×T of two well-ordered sets having these order types. Start by putting a partial order on this cartesian product by using just the product order (compare two pairs if and only if each of the two coordinates is comparable). Now consider the order types of all well-orders which extend this partial order: the least upper bound of all these ordinals (which is, actually, not merely a least upper bound but actually a greatest element) is the natural product. There is also an inductive definition of the natural product (by mutual induction), but it is somewhat tedious to write down and we will not do so (see the article on surreal numbers for the definition in that context, which, however, uses Conway subtraction, something which obviously cannot be defined on ordinals).
The natural product is associative and commutative and distributes over the natural sum: it is always greater or equal to the usual product, but it may be greater. For example, the natural product of ω and 2 is ω·2 (the usual product), but this is also the natural product of 2 and ω.
Yet another way to define the natural sum and product of two ordinals α and β is to use the Cantor normal form: one can find a sequence of ordinals γ1 > ... > γn and two sequences (k1, ... , kn) and (j1, ... , jn) of natural numbers (including zero, but satisfying ki+ji >0 for all i) such that
and defines
References
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-86839-9.
This entry is from Wikipedia, the leading user-contributed encyclopedia. It may not have been reviewed by professional editors (see full disclaimer)