Supercompact cardinal - Wikipedia
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In set theory, a supercompact cardinal is a type of large cardinal independently introduced by Solovay and Reinhardt.[1] They display a variety of reflection properties.
If is any ordinal,
is
-supercompact means that there exists an elementary embedding
from the universe
into a transitive inner model
with critical point
,
and
That is, contains all of its
-sequences. Then
is supercompact means that it is
-supercompact for all ordinals
.
Alternatively, an uncountable cardinal is supercompact if for every
such that
there exists a normal measure over
, in the following sense.
is defined as follows:
.
An ultrafilter over
is fine if it is
-complete and
, for every
. A normal measure over
is a fine ultrafilter
over
with the additional property that every function
such that
is constant on a set in
. Here "constant on a set in
" means that there is
such that
.
Supercompact cardinals have reflection properties. If a cardinal with some property (say a 3-huge cardinal) that is witnessed by a structure of limited rank exists above a supercompact cardinal , then a cardinal with that property exists below
. For example, if
is supercompact and the generalized continuum hypothesis (GCH) holds below
then it holds everywhere because a bijection between the powerset of
and a cardinal at least
would be a witness of limited rank for the failure of GCH at
so it would also have to exist below
.
Finding a canonical inner model for supercompact cardinals is one of the major problems of inner model theory.
The least supercompact cardinal is the least such that for every structure
with cardinality of the domain
, and for every
sentence
such that
, there exists a substructure
with smaller domain (i.e.
) that satisfies
.[2]
Supercompactness has a combinatorial characterization similar to the property of being ineffable. Let be the set of all nonempty subsets of
which have cardinality
. A cardinal
is supercompact iff for every set
(equivalently every cardinal
), for every function
, if
for all
, then there is some
such that
is stationary.[3]
Magidor obtained a variant of the tree property which holds for an inaccessible cardinal iff it is supercompact.[4]
- Drake, F. R. (1974). Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; V. 76). Elsevier Science Ltd. ISBN 0-444-10535-2.
- Jech, Thomas (2002). Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded). Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
- Kanamori, Akihiro (2003). The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 3-540-00384-3.
- ^ A. Kanamori, "Kunen and set theory", pp.2450--2451. Topology and its Applications, vol. 158 (2011).
- ^ Magidor, M. (1971). "On the Role of Supercompact and Extendible Cardinals in Logic". Israel Journal of Mathematics. 10 (2): 147–157. doi:10.1007/BF02771565.
- ^ M. Magidor, Combinatorial Characterization of Supercompact Cardinals, pp.281--282. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 42 no. 1, 1974.
- ^ S. Hachtman, S. Sinapova, "The super tree property at the successor of a singular". Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol 236, iss. 1 (2020), pp.473--500.