ncatlab.org

Top (Rev #31) in nLab

Context

Topology

topology (point-set topology, point-free topology)

see also differential topology, algebraic topology, functional analysis and topological homotopy theory

Introduction

Basic concepts

Universal constructions

Extra stuff, structure, properties

Examples

Basic statements

Theorems

Analysis Theorems

topological homotopy theory

Contents

Definition

Top denotes the category whose objects are topological spaces and whose morphisms are continuous functions between them. Its isomorphisms are the homeomorphisms.

Often one considers (sometimes by default) subcategories of nice topological spaces such as compactly generated topological spaces, notably because these are cartesian closed. There other other convenient categories of topological spaces. With any one such choice understood, it is often useful to regard it as “the” category of topological spaces.

The homotopy category of TopTop given by its localization at the weak homotopy equivalences is the classical homotopy category Ho(Top). This is the central object of study in homotopy theory, see also at classical model structure on topological spaces. The simplicial localization of Top at the weak homotopy equivalences is the archetypical (∞,1)-category, equivalent to ∞Grpd (see at homotopy hypothesis).

Properties

Universal constructions

We discuss universal constructions in Top, such as limits/colimits, etc. The following definition suggests that universal constructions be seen in the context of TopTop as a topological concrete category (see Proposition 4 below):

Definition

Let {X i=(S i,τ i)∈Top} i∈I\{X_i = (S_i,\tau_i) \in Top\}_{i \in I} be a class of topological spaces, and let S∈SetS \in Set be a bare set. Then

  • For {S→f iS i} i∈I\{S \stackrel{f_i}{\to} S_i \}_{i \in I} a set of functions out of SS, the initial topology τ initial({f i} i∈I)\tau_{initial}(\{f_i\}_{i \in I}) is the topology on SS with the minimum collection of open subsets such that all f i:(S,τ initial({f i} i∈I))→X if_i \colon (S,\tau_{initial}(\{f_i\}_{i \in I}))\to X_i are continuous.

  • For {S i→f iS} i∈I\{S_i \stackrel{f_i}{\to} S\}_{i \in I} a set of functions into SS, the final topology τ final({f i} i∈I)\tau_{final}(\{f_i\}_{i \in I}) is the topology on SS with the maximum collection of open subsets such that all f i:X i→(S,τ final({f i} i∈I))f_i \colon X_i \to (S,\tau_{final}(\{f_i\}_{i \in I})) are continuous.

Example

For XX a single topological space, and ι S:S↪U(X)\iota_S \colon S \hookrightarrow U(X) a subset of its underlying set, then the initial topology τ intial(ι S)\tau_{intial}(\iota_S), def. 1, is the subspace topology, making

ι S:(S,τ initial(ι S))↪X \iota_S \;\colon\; (S, \tau_{initial}(\iota_S)) \hookrightarrow X

a topological subspace inclusion.

Example

Conversely, for p S:U(X)⟶Sp_S \colon U(X) \longrightarrow S an epimorphism, then the final topology τ final(p S)\tau_{final}(p_S) on SS is the quotient topology.

Proposition

Let II be a small category and let X •:I⟶TopX_\bullet \colon I \longrightarrow Top be an II-diagram in Top (a functor from II to TopTop), with components denoted X i=(S i,τ i)X_i = (S_i, \tau_i), where S i∈SetS_i \in Set and τ i\tau_i a topology on S iS_i. Then:

  1. The limit of X •X_\bullet exists and is given by the topological space whose underlying set is the limit in Set of the underlying sets in the diagram, and whose topology is the initial topology, def. 1, for the functions p ip_i which are the limiting cone components:

    lim⟵ i∈IS i p i↙ ↘ p j S i ⟶ S j. \array{ && \underset{\longleftarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i \\ & {}^{\mathllap{p_i}}\swarrow && \searrow^{\mathrlap{p_j}} \\ S_i && \underset{}{\longrightarrow} && S_j } \,.

    Hence

    lim⟵ i∈IX i≃(lim⟵ i∈IS i,τ initial({p i} i∈I)) \underset{\longleftarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} X_i \simeq \left(\underset{\longleftarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i,\; \tau_{initial}(\{p_i\}_{i \in I})\right)

  2. The colimit of X •X_\bullet exists and is the topological space whose underlying set is the colimit in Set of the underlying diagram of sets, and whose topology is the final topology, def. 1 for the component maps ι i\iota_i of the colimiting cocone

    S i ⟶ S j ι i↘ ↙ ι j lim⟶ i∈IS i. \array{ S_i && \longrightarrow && S_j \\ & {}_{\mathllap{\iota_i}}\searrow && \swarrow_{\mathrlap{\iota_j}} \\ && \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i } \,.

    Hence

    lim⟶ i∈IX i≃(lim⟶ i∈IS i,τ final({ι i} i∈I)) \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} X_i \simeq \left(\underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i,\; \tau_{final}(\{\iota_i\}_{i \in I})\right)

(e.g. Bourbaki 71, section I.4)

Proof

The required universal property of (lim⟵ i∈IS i,τ initial({p i} i∈I))\left(\underset{\longleftarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i,\; \tau_{initial}(\{p_i\}_{i \in I})\right) is immediate: for

(S,τ) f i↙ ↘ f j X i ⟶ X i \array{ && (S,\tau) \\ & {}^{\mathllap{f_i}}\swarrow && \searrow^{\mathrlap{f_j}} \\ X_i && \underset{}{\longrightarrow} && X_i }

any cone over the diagram, then by construction there is a unique function of underlying sets S⟶lim⟵ i∈IS iS \longrightarrow \underset{\longleftarrow}{\lim}_{i \in I} S_i making the required diagrams commute, and so all that is required is that this unique function is always continuous. But this is precisely what the initial topology ensures.

The case of the colimit is formally dual.

Example

The limit over the empty diagram in TopTop is the point *\ast with its unique topology.

Example

For {X i} i∈I\{X_i\}_{i \in I} a set of topological spaces, their coproduct ⊔i∈IX i∈Top\underset{i \in I}{\sqcup} X_i \in Top is their disjoint union.

In particular:

Example

The equalizer of two continuous functions f,g:X⟶⟶Yf, g \colon X \stackrel{\longrightarrow}{\longrightarrow} Y in TopTop is the equalizer of the underlying functions of sets

eq(f,g)↪S X⟶g⟶fS Y eq(f,g) \hookrightarrow S_X \stackrel{\overset{f}{\longrightarrow}}{\underset{g}{\longrightarrow}} S_Y

(hence the largets subset of S XS_X on which both functions coincide) and equipped with the subspace topology, example 1.

Example

The coequalizer of two continuous functions f,g:X⟶⟶Yf, g \colon X \stackrel{\longrightarrow}{\longrightarrow} Y in TopTop is the coequalizer of the underlying functions of sets

S X⟶g⟶fS Y⟶coeq(f,g) S_X \stackrel{\overset{f}{\longrightarrow}}{\underset{g}{\longrightarrow}} S_Y \longrightarrow coeq(f,g)

(hence the quotient set by the equivalence relation generated by f(x)∼g(x)f(x) \sim g(x) for all x∈Xx \in X) and equipped with the quotient topology, example 2.

Example

For

A ⟶g Y f↓ X \array{ A &\overset{g}{\longrightarrow}& Y \\ {}^{\mathllap{f}}\downarrow \\ X }

two continuous functions out of the same domain, then the colimit under this diagram is also called the pushout, denoted

A ⟶g Y f↓ ↓ g *f X ⟶ X⊔ AY.. \array{ A &\overset{g}{\longrightarrow}& Y \\ {}^{\mathllap{f}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{g_\ast f}} \\ X &\longrightarrow& X \sqcup_A Y \,. } \,.

(Here g *fg_\ast f is also called the pushout of ff, or the cobase change of ff along gg.) If gg is an inclusion, one also write X∪ fYX \cup_f Y and calls this the attaching space.

By example 8 the pushout/attaching space is the quotient topological space

X⊔ AY≃(X⊔Y)/∼ X \sqcup_A Y \simeq (X\sqcup Y)/\sim

of the disjoint union of XX and YY subject to the equivalence relation which identifies a point in XX with a point in YY if they have the same pre-image in AA.

(graphics from Aguilar-Gitler-Prieto 02)

Example

As an important special case of example 9, let

i n:S n−1⟶D n i_n \colon S^{n-1}\longrightarrow D^n

be the canonical inclusion of the standard (n-1)-sphere as the boundary of the standard n-disk (both regarded as topological spaces with their subspace topology as subspaces of the Cartesian space ℝ n\mathbb{R}^n).

Then the colimit in Top under the diagram, i.e. the pushout of i ni_n along itself,

{D n⟵i nS n−1⟶i nD n}, \left\{ D^n \overset{i_n}{\longleftarrow} S^{n-1} \overset{i_n}{\longrightarrow} D^n \right\} \,,

is the n-sphere S nS^n:

S n−1 ⟶i n D n i n↓ (po) ↓ D n ⟶ S n. \array{ S^{n-1} &\overset{i_n}{\longrightarrow}& D^n \\ {}^{\mathllap{i_n}}\downarrow &(po)& \downarrow \\ D^n &\longrightarrow& S^n } \,.

(graphics from Ueno-Shiga-Morita 95)

Relation with SetSet

Definition

Write

U:Top⟶Set U \colon Top \longrightarrow Set

for the forgetful functor that sends a topological space X=(S,τ)X = (S,\tau) to its underlying set U(X)=S∈SetU(X) = S \in Set and which regards a continuous function as a plain function on the underlying sets.

Prop. 1 means in particular that:

(But it does not create or reflect them.)

Mono-/Epimorphisms, Quotients and Intersections

For proof see there.

References

See also

  • Marcelo Aguilar, Samuel Gitler, Carlos Prieto, section 12 of Algebraic topology from a homotopical viewpoint, Springer (2002) (toc pdf)

An axiomatic desciption of TopTop along the lines of ETCS for Set is discussed in

  • Dana Schlomiuk, An elementary theory of the category of topological space, Transactions of the AMS, volume 149 (1970)

Revision on May 3, 2016 at 11:22:55 by Urs Schreiber See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.