Quillen adjunction in nLab
Context
Model category theory
model category, model ∞ \infty -category
Definitions
Morphisms
Universal constructions
Refinements
Producing new model structures
Presentation of (∞,1)(\infty,1)-categories
Model structures
for ∞\infty-groupoids
-
on chain complexes/model structure on cosimplicial abelian groups
related by the Dold-Kan correspondence
for equivariant ∞\infty-groupoids
for rational ∞\infty-groupoids
for rational equivariant ∞\infty-groupoids
for nn-groupoids
for ∞\infty-groups
for ∞\infty-algebras
general ∞\infty-algebras
specific ∞\infty-algebras
for stable/spectrum objects
for (∞,1)(\infty,1)-categories
for stable (∞,1)(\infty,1)-categories
for (∞,1)(\infty,1)-operads
for (n,r)(n,r)-categories
for (∞,1)(\infty,1)-sheaves / ∞\infty-stacks
Contents
Idea
Quillen adjunctions are one convenient notion of morphisms between model categories. They present adjoint (∞,1)-functors between the (∞,1)-categories presented by the model categories.
Definition
Proof
Observe that
-
(i) A left adjoint LL between model categories preserves acyclic cofibrations precisely if its right adjoint RR preserves fibrations.
-
(ii) A left adjoint LL between model categories preserves cofibrations precisely if its right adjoint RR preserves acyclic fibrations.
We discuss statement (i), statement (ii) is formally dual. So let f:A→Bf\colon A \to B be an acyclic cofibration in 𝒟\mathcal{D} and g:X→Yg \colon X \to Y a fibration in 𝒞\mathcal{C}. Then for every commuting diagram as on the left of the following, its (L⊣R)(L\dashv R)-adjunct is a commuting diagram as on the right here:
A ⟶ R(X) f↓ ↓ R(g) B ⟶ R(Y),L(A) ⟶ X L(f)↓ ↓ g L(B) ⟶ Y. \array{ A &\longrightarrow& R(X) \\ {}^{\mathllap{f}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{R(g)}} \\ B &\longrightarrow& R(Y) } \;\;\;\;\;\; \,, \;\;\;\;\;\; \array{ L(A) &\longrightarrow& X \\ {}^{\mathllap{L(f)}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{g}} \\ L(B) &\longrightarrow& Y } \,.
If LL preserves acyclic cofibrations, then the diagram on the right has a lift, and so the (L⊣R)(L\dashv R)-adjunct of that lift is a lift of the left diagram. This shows that R(g)R(g) has the right lifting property against all acylic cofibrations and hence is a fibration. Conversely, if RR preserves fibrations, the same argument run from right to left gives that LL preserves acyclic fibrations.
Now by repeatedly applying (i) and (ii), all four conditions in question are seen to be equivalent.
Properties
Derived adjunction
Proof
To show this for instance for RR, we may argue as in a category of fibrant objects and apply the factorization lemma which shows that every weak equivalence between fibrant objects may be factored, up to homotopy, as a span of acyclic fibrations.
These weak equivalences are preserved by the right Quillen property of RR and hence the claim follows by 2-out-of-3.
For LL we apply the formally dual argument.
Behaviour under Bousfield localization
Proposition
Given a Quillen adjunction
(L⊣R):𝒞⊥ Qu⟶R⟵L𝒟 (L \dashv R) \;\;\;\colon\;\;\; \mathcal{C} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;\;\; R \;\;\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;\;\; L \;\;\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\bot_{\mathrlap{{}_{Qu}}}} \mathcal{D}
and S⊂Mor(𝒟)S \subset Mor(\mathcal{D}) is a set of morphisms such that
-
the left Bousfield localization of 𝒟\mathcal{D} at SS exists,
-
the derived image 𝕃L(S)\mathbb{L}L(S) of SS lands in the weak equivalences of 𝒞\mathcal{C},
then the Quillen adjunction descends to the Bousfield localization 𝒟 S\mathcal{D}_S
(L⊣R):𝒞⊥ Qu⟶R⟵L𝒟 S. (L \dashv R) \;\;\;\colon\;\;\; \mathcal{C} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;\;\; R \;\;\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;\;\; L \;\;\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\bot_{\mathrlap{{}_{Qu}}}} \mathcal{D}_S \,.
This appears as (Hirschhorn, prop. 3.3.18)
Of sSetsSet-enriched adjunctions
Of particular interest are SSet-enriched adjunctions between simplicial model categories: simplicial Quillen adjunctions.
These present adjoint (∞,1)-functors, as the first proposition below asserts.
Proof
This is proposition 5.2.4.6 in HTT.
The following proposition states conditions under which a Quillen adjunction may be detected already from knowing of the right adjoint only that it preserves fibrant objects (instead of all fibrations).
This appears as HTT, cor. A.3.7.2.
See simplicial Quillen adjunction for more details.
Associated (infinity,1)-adjunction
See (Mazel-Gee 16, Theorem 2.1). (This is also asserted as (Hinich 14, Proposition 1.5.1), but it is not completely proved there – see (Mazel-Gee 16, Remark 2.3).)
For simplicial model categories with sSet-enriched Quillen adjunctions between them, this is also in (Lurie, prop. 5.2.4.6).
See also at derived functor – As functors on infinity-categories
References
See the references at model category. For instance
- Philip Hirschhorn, Model categories and their localization
- Peter May, Kate Ponto, Section 16.2 of: More concise algebraic topology, University of Chicago Press (2012) (ISBN:9780226511795, pdf)
The proof that a Quillen adjunction of model categories induces an adjunction of (infinity,1)-categories is recorded in
- Aaron Mazel-Gee, Quillen adjunctions induce adjunctions of quasicategories, New York Journal of Mathematics Volume 22 (2016) 57-93 (arXiv:1501.03146, publisher)
and this question is also partially addressed in
- Vladimir Hinich, Dwyer-Kan Localization Revisited, Homology, Homotopy and Applications Volume 18 (2016) Number 1 (arXiv:1311.4128, doi:10.4310/HHA.2016.v18.n1.a3)
The case for simplicial model categories is also in
Last revised on May 13, 2023 at 13:38:57. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.