category of sheaves in nLab
Context
Topos Theory
Background
Toposes
Internal Logic
Topos morphisms
Cohomology and homotopy
In higher category theory
Theorems
Locality and descent
Contents
Idea
This entry is about the properties and the characterization of the category Sh(S)Sh(S) of (set-valued) sheaves on a (small) site SS, which is a Grothendieck topos. Among other things it gives a definition and a characterization of the notion of sheaf itself, but for more details on sheaves themselves see there.
Definition
Let (C,J)(C,J) be a site: a (small) category equipped with a coverage.
This appears for instance as (Johnstone, corollary C.2.1.11). See also Lawvere-Tierney topology.
Equivalent characterizations
As localizations
Proposition
The category of sheaves is equivalent to the homotopy category of the category with weak equivalences PSh(C)PSh(C) with the weak equivalences given by W=W = local isomorphisms
Sh(S)≃Ho PSh(S)=PSh(C)[local isomorphisms] −1. Sh(S) \simeq Ho_{PSh(S)} = PSh(C)[\text{local isomorphisms}]^{-1} \,.
The converse is also true: for every left exact functor L:PSh(S)→PSh(S)L : PSh(S) \to PSh(S) (preserving finite limits) which is left adjoint to the inclusion of its image, there is a Grothendieck topology on SS such that the image of LL is the category of sheaves on SS with respect to that topology.
We spell out proofs of some of the above claims.
Let CC be a small category and
i:ℰ↪[C op,Set] i : \mathcal{E} \hookrightarrow [C^{op}, Set]
a reflective subcategory, hence a full subcategory with a left adjoint L:[C op,Set]→ℰL : [C^{op}, Set] \to \mathcal{E}, such that moreover LL preserves finite limits.
Write W:=L −1(isos)⊂Mor([C op,Set])W := L^{-1}(isos) \subset Mor([C^{op}, Set]) for the class of morphisms in [C op,Set][C^{op}, Set] that are sent to isomorphisms by LL.
Proposition
A presheaf A∈[C op,Set]A \in [C^{op}, Set] is in ℰ\mathcal{E} (meaning: in the essential image of ii) precisely if for all f:X→Yf : X \to Y in WW the induced function
Hom(f,A):Hom(Y,A)→Hom(X,A) Hom(f,A) : Hom(Y,A) \to Hom(X,A)
is a bijection.
Proof
If A≃iA^A \simeq i \hat A, then by the (L⊣i)(L \dashv i)-adjunction isomorphism we have
Hom(f,iA^)≃ℰ(L(f),A). Hom(f, i \hat A) \simeq \mathcal{E}(L(f), A) \,.
But by assumption L(f)L(f) is an isomorphism, so the claim is immediate.
Conversely, if for all ff the function Hom(f,A)Hom(f,A) is a bijection, define A^:=L(A)\hat A := L(A) and let ϵ A:A→iL(A) \epsilon_A : A \to i L(A) be the (L⊣i)(L \dashv i)-unit.
By the assumption that ii is a full and faithful functor and basic properties of adjoint functors we have that the counit
Li→Id L i \to Id
is a natural isomorphism. By the zig-zag law the composite
LA→Lϵ ALiLA→≃LA L A \stackrel{L \epsilon_A}{\to} L i L A \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} L A
is the identity and therefore LϵL \epsilon is an isomorphism and so ϵ A\epsilon_A is in WW, under our assumption on AA.
Using this it follows that
Hom(ϵ A,A):Hom(iLA,A)→≃Hom(A,A) Hom(\epsilon_A, A) : Hom(i L A, A) \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} Hom(A,A)
is an isomorphism. Write k A:iLA→Ak_A : i L A \to A for the preimage of id Aid_A under this isomorphism, which is therefore a left inverse of ϵ A\epsilon_A. This immediately implies that also k Ak_A is in WW, and so we can enter the same argument with k Ak_A to find that it has a left inverse itself. But this means that k Ak_A is in fact an isomorphism and hence so is ϵA\epsilon A, which thus exhibits AA as being in the essential image of ii.
Proposition
A morphism f:X→Yf : X \to Y is in WW precisely if for every morphism z:j(c)→Yz : j(c) \to Y with representable domain, the pullback z *fz^* f in
X× Yj(c) → X z *f↓ ↓ f j(c) →z Y \array{ X \times_Y j(c) &\to& X \\ {}^{\mathllap{z^* f}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{f}} \\ j(c) &\stackrel{z}{\to}& Y }
is in WW.
Proof
Assume first that ff is in WW. Since by assumption LL preserves finite limits, it follows that
L(X× Yj(c)) → LX L(z *f)↓ ↓ Lf L(j(c)) →Lz LY \array{ L(X \times_Y j(c)) &\to& L X \\ {}^{\mathllap{L(z^* f)}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{L f}} \\ L(j(c)) &\stackrel{L z}{\to}& L Y }
is still a pullback diagram in ℰ\mathcal{E} and hence that L(z *f)L(z^* f) is the pullback of the isomorphism LfL f and thus itself an isomorphism. Therefore z *fz^* f is in WW.
Conversely, suppose that all these pullbacks are in WW. Then use the “co-Yoneda lemma” to write the presheaf YY as a colimit over all representables mapping into it
lim → j(c i)→z iYj(c)→≃Y. {\lim_\to}_{j(c_i) \stackrel{z_i}{\to} Y} j(c) \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} Y \,.
Forming the pullback along ff, using that in a topos (such as our presheaf topos) colimits are preserved by pullbacks, we get
lim → if *j(c i) →≃ X lim → iz i *f↓ ↓ f lim → ij(c i) →≃ Y. \array{ {\lim_\to}_i f^* j(c_i) &\stackrel{\simeq}{\to}& X \\ {}^{\mathllap{{\lim_\to}_i z_i^* f}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{f}} \\ {\lim_\to}_i j(c_i) &\stackrel{\simeq}{\to}& Y } \,.
Since LL preserves all colimits and finite limits, we also get
lim → iL(f *j(c i)) →≃ L(X) lim → iL(z i *f)↓ ↓ L(f) lim → iL(j(c i)) →≃ L(Y). \array{ {\lim_\to}_i L(f^* j(c_i)) &\stackrel{\simeq}{\to}& L(X) \\ {}^{\mathllap{{\lim_\to}_i L(z_i^* f)}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{L(f)}} \\ {\lim_\to}_i L(j(c_i)) &\stackrel{\simeq}{\to}& L(Y) } \,.
Since by assumption now all L(z i *f)L(z_i^* f ) are isomorphisms, also lim → iL(z i *f){\lim_\to}_i L(z_i^* f) is an isomorphism and hence three sides of the above square are isomorphisms. Therefore also L(f)L(f) is and hence ff is in WW.
Proof
We check the list of axioms, given at Grothendieck topology:
-
Pullbacks of covering sieves are covering :
First of all, the pullback of a sieve along a morphism of representables is still a sieve, because monomorphisms are (as discussed there) stable under pullback.
Next, since LL preserves finite limits, LL applied to the pullback sieve is the pullback of an isomorphism, hence is an isomorphism, hence the pullback sieve is in WW.
-
The maximal sieve is covering. Clear: LL applied to an isomorphism is an isomorphism.
-
Two sieves cover precisely if their intersection covers. This is again due to the pullback-stability of elements of WW, due to the preservation of finite limits by LL.
-
If all pullbacks of a sieve along morphisms of a covering sieve are covering, then the original sieve was covering .
This is the same argument as in the second part of the proof of prop. .
Proof
By prop. and prop. we are reduced to showing that an object AA is in ℰ\mathcal{E} already if for all monomorphisms ff in WW the function Hom(f,A)Hom(f,A) is a bijection.
(…)
As toposes
Categories of sheaves are examples of categories that are toposes: they are the Grothendieck toposes characterized among all toposes as those satisfying Giraud's axioms.
This appears for instance as (Johnstone, corollary C.2.1.11).
As accessible reflective subcategories
See also at reflective sub-(∞,1)-category.
Properties
Dependence on the site
Definition
For (L⊣i):ℰ↪←L(L \dashv i) : \mathcal{E} \stackrel{\overset{L}{\leftarrow}}{\hookrightarrow} a category of sheaves and (C,J)(C,J) a site such that we have an equivalence of categories ℰ≃Sh J(C)\mathcal{E} \simeq Sh_J(C) we say that CC is a site of definition for the topos ℰ\mathcal{E}.
Definition
For (C,J)(C,J) a site with coverage JJ and D→CD \to C any subcategory, the induced coverage J DJ_D on DD has as covering sieves the intersections of the covering sieves of CC with the morphisms in DD.
Definition
Let (C,J)(C,J) be a site (possibly large). A subcategory D→CD \to C (not necessarily full) is called a dense sub-site with the induced coverage J DJ_D if
Theorem
(comparison lemma)
Let (C,J)(C,J) be a (possibly large) site with CC a locally small category and let f:D→Cf : D \to C be a small dense sub-site. The pair of adjoint functors
(f *⊣f *):PSh(D)→f *←f *PSh(C) (f^* \dashv f_*) : PSh(D) \stackrel{\overset{f^*}{\leftarrow}}{\underset{f_*}{\to}} PSh(C)
with f *f^* given by precomposition with ff and f *f_* given by right Kan extension induces an equivalence of categories between the categories of sheaves
(f *⊣f *):Sh J D(D)≃→f *←f *Sh JC. (f_* \dashv f^*) : Sh_{J_D}(D) \underoverset {\underset{f_*}{\to}}{\overset{f^*} {\leftarrow}} {\simeq} Sh_J{C} \,.
This appears as (Johnstone, theorm C2.2.3).
Examples
-
Let XX be a locale with frame Op(X)Op(X) regarded as a site with the canonical coverage ({U i→U}\{U_i \to U\} covers if the join of the U iU_i is UU). Let bOp(X)bOp(X) be a basis for the topology of XX: a complete join-semilattice such that every object of Op(X)Op(X) is the join of objects of bOp(X)bOp(X). Then bOp(X)bOp(X) is a dense sub-site.
- For XX a locally contractible space, Op(X)Op(X) its category of open subsets and cOp(X)cOp(X) the full subcategory of contractible open subsets, we have that cOp(X)cOp(X) is a dense sub-site.
-
For C=TopManifoldC = TopManifold the category of all paracompact topological manifolds equipped with the open cover coverage, the category CartSp top{}_{top} is a dense sub-site: every paracompact manifold has a good open cover by open balls homeomorphic to a Cartesian space.
-
Similaryl for C=C = Diff the category of smooth manifolds equipped with the good open cover coverage, the full subcategory CartSp smooth{}_{smooth} is a dense sub-site.
Limits and colimits
Beware that, in general, constant presheaves need not be sheaves. But the presheaf constant on the singleton set is always a sheaf:
Epi- mono- and isomorphisms
Proposition
Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a small site and let Sh(𝒞)Sh(\mathcal{C}) be its category of sheaves. Let f:X→Yf \colon X \to Y be a homomorphism of sheaves, hence a morphism in Sh(𝒞)Sh(\mathcal{C}). Then:
-
ff is a monomorphism or isomorphism precisely if it is so globally in that for each object U∈𝒞U \in \mathcal{C} in the site, then the component f U:X(U)→Y(U)f_U \colon X(U) \to Y(U) is an injection or bijection of sets, respectively.
-
ff is an epimorphism precisely if it is so locally, in that: for all U∈CU \in C and every element y∈Y(U)y \in Y(U) there is a covering {p i:U i→U} i∈I\{p_i : U_i \to U\}_{i \in I} such that for all i∈Ii \in I the element Y(p i)(y)Y(p_i)(y) is in the image of f(U i):X(U i)→Y(U i)f(U_i) : X(U_i) \to Y(U_i).
But if {x i} i∈I\{x_i\}_{i \in I} is a set of points of a topos for Sh(𝒞)Sh(\mathcal{C}) such that these are enough points (def.) then the morphism ff is epi/mono/iso precisely it is is so an all stalks, hence precisely if
x i *f:x i *X⟶x i *Y x_i^\ast f \;\colon\; x_i^\ast X \longrightarrow x_i^\ast Y
is a surjection/injection/bijection of sets, respectively, for all i∈Ii \in I.
Exactness properties
Every sheaf topos satisfies the following exactness properties. it is an
-
category of sheaves
References
-
Francis Borceux, vol 3 of Handbook of Categorical Algebra, Cambridge University Press (1994)
-
Peter Johnstone, sections A.4 and C.2 in Sketches of an Elephant
-
The Stacks Project, Sites and sheaves (pdf)
The characterization of sheaf toposes and Grothendieck topologies in terms of left exact reflective subcategories of a presheaf category is also in
where it is implied by the combination of Corollary VII 4.7 and theorem V.4.1.
There is also a direct proof in Shane Kelly, What is the relationship between Grothendieck pretopologies and Grothendieck topologies? (web) .
The characterization of Sh(S)Sh(S) as the homotopy category of PSh(S)PSh(S) with respect to local isomorphisms is emphasized at the beginning of the text
- Bertrand Toen, Stacks and non-abelian cohomology (web) .
Details are in
It’s a bit odd that the full final statement does not seem to be stated there explicitly, but all the ingredients are discussed:
-
exercise 16.7 shows that sheafification inverts precisely the local isomorphisms, so that in particular every local isomorphism between sheaves is an isomorphism;
-
lemma 16.3.2 states that the unit of the adjunction Id PSh(S)→i∘(−)¯:PSh(S)→PSh(S)Id_{PSh(S)} \rightarrow i \circ \bar{(-)} : PSh(S) \to PSh(S) is componentwise a local isomorphism;
-
using this corollary 7.2.2 says that Sh(S)≃Ho PSh(S)Sh(S) \simeq Ho_{PSh(S)} with the homotopy category Ho PSh(S)Ho_{PSh(S)} formed using local isomorphisms as weak equivalences.
Letcure notes:
- Pierre Schapira, An Introduction to Categories and Sheaves, lecture notes (2023) [pdf, pdf]
Last revised on June 19, 2024 at 08:50:19. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.