span in nLab
This entry is about the notion of spans/correspondences which generalizes that of relations. For spans in vector spaces or modules, see linear span.
Context
Relations
Rel, bicategory of relations, allegory
Types of Binary relation
-
left and right euclidean;
-
extensional, well-founded relations.
In higher category theory
Set theory
- fundamentals of set theory
- material set theory
- presentations of set theory
- structuralism in set theory
- class-set theory
- constructive set theory
- algebraic set theory
Type theory
natural deduction metalanguage, practical foundations
type theory (dependent, intensional, observational type theory, homotopy type theory)
Category theory
2-Category theory
Definitions
Transfors between 2-categories
Morphisms in 2-categories
Structures in 2-categories
Limits in 2-categories
Structures on 2-categories
Contents
Definition
In set theory
In set theory, a span or correspondence between sets AA and BB is a set CC with a function R:C→A×BR:C \to A \times B to the product set A×BA \times B. A span between a set AA and AA itself is a directed pseudograph, which is used to define categories in set theory.
In dependent type theory
In dependent type theory, there is a distinction between a span, a multivalued partial function, and a correspondence:
-
A span between types AA and BB is a type CC with families of elements x:C⊢g(x):Ax:C \vdash g(x):A and x:C⊢h(x):Bx:C \vdash h(x):B
-
A multivalued partial function from type AA to type BB is a type family x:A⊢P(x)x:A \vdash P(x) with a family of elements x:A,p:P(x)⊢f(x,p):Bx:A, p:P(x) \vdash f(x, p):B
-
A correspondence between types AA and BB is a type family x:A,y:B⊢R(x,y)x:A, y:B \vdash R(x, y).
However, from any one of the above structures, one could get the other two structures, provided one has identity types and dependent pair types in the dependent type theory. Given a type family x:A⊢P(x)x:A \vdash P(x), let z:∑ x:AP(x)⊢π 1(z):Az:\sum_{x:A} P(x) \vdash \pi_1(z):A and z:∑ x:AP(x)⊢π 2(z):P(π 1(z))z:\sum_{x:A} P(x) \vdash \pi_2(z):P(\pi_1(z)) be the dependent pair projections for the dependent pair type ∑ x:AP(x)\sum_{x:A} P(x).
-
From every span one could get a multivalued partial function by defining the type family x:A⊢P(x)x:A \vdash P(x) as P(x)≔∑ y:Cg(y)= AxP(x) \coloneqq \sum_{y:C} g(y) =_A x and the family of elements x:A,p:P(x)⊢f(x,p):Bx:A, p:P(x) \vdash f(x, p):B as f(x,p)≔h(π 1(x))f(x, p) \coloneqq h(\pi_1(x)).
-
From every multivalued partial function one could get a span by defining the type CC as C≔∑ x:AP(x)C \coloneqq \sum_{x:A} P(x) and the family of elements x:C⊢g(x):Ax:C \vdash g(x):A as g(x)≔π 1(x)g(x) \coloneqq \pi_1(x).
-
From every multivalued partial function one could get a correspondence by defining the type family x:A,y:B⊢R(x,y)x:A, y:B \vdash R(x, y) as R(x,y)≔∑ p:P(x)f(x,p)= ByR(x, y) \coloneqq \sum_{p:P(x)} f(x, p) =_B y.
-
From every correspondence one could get a multivalued partial function by defining the type family x:A⊢P(x)x:A \vdash P(x) as P(x)≔∑ y:BR(x,y)P(x) \coloneqq \sum_{y:B} R(x, y), and the family of elements x:A,p:P(x)⊢h(x,p):Bx:A, p:P(x) \vdash h(x, p):B as h(x,p)≔π 1(p)h(x, p) \coloneqq \pi_1(p)
-
From every span one could get a correspondence by defining the type family x:A,y:B⊢R(x,y)x:A, y:B \vdash R(x, y) as R(x,y)≔∑ z:C(g(z)= Ax)×(h(z)= By)R(x, y) \coloneqq \sum_{z:C} (g(z) =_A x) \times (h(z) =_B y).
-
From every correspondence one could get a span by defining the type CC as C≔∑ x:A∑ y:BR(x,y)C \coloneqq \sum_{x:A} \sum_{y:B} R(x, y), the family of elements z:C⊢g(z):Az:C \vdash g(z):A as g(z)≔π 1(z)g(z) \coloneqq \pi_1(z), and the function z:C⊢h(z):Bz:C \vdash h(z):B as h(z)≔π 1(π 2(z))h(z) \coloneqq \pi_1(\pi_2(z))
Given types AA, BB, and CC and spans (D,x:D⊢g D(x):A,x:D⊢h D(x):B)(D, x:D \vdash g_D(x):A, x:D \vdash h_D(x):B) between AA and BB and (E,y:E⊢g E(y):B,y:E⊢h E(y):C)(E, y:E \vdash g_E(y):B, y:E \vdash h_E(y):C) between BB and CC, there is a span
(E∘D,z:E∘D⊢g E∘D(z):A,z:E∘D⊢h E∘D(z):C)(E \circ D, z:E \circ D \vdash g_{E \circ D}(z):A, z:E \circ D \vdash h_{E \circ D}(z):C)
defined by
E∘D≔∑ x:D∑ y:Eh D(x)= Bg E(y)E \circ D \coloneqq \sum_{x:D} \sum_{y:E} h_D(x) =_B g_E(y)
z:E∘D⊢g E∘D(z)≔g D(π 1(z))z:E \circ D \vdash g_{E \circ D}(z) \coloneqq g_D(\pi_1(z))
z:E∘D⊢h E∘D(z)≔h E(π 1(π 2(π 1(z))(z)))z:E \circ D \vdash h_{E \circ D}(z) \coloneqq h_E(\pi_1(\pi_2(\pi_1(z))(z)))
Given types AA, BB, and CC and correspondences x:A,y:B⊢R(x,y)x:A, y:B \vdash R(x, y) and y:B,z:C⊢S(y,z)y:B, z:C \vdash S(y, z), there is a correspondence x:A,z:C⊢(S∘R)(x,z)x:A, z:C \vdash (S \circ R)(x, z) defined by
(S∘R)(x,z)≔∑ y:BR(x,y)×S(y,z)(S \circ R)(x, z) \coloneqq \sum_{y:B} R(x, y) \times S(y, z)
In category theory
In any category CC, a span, or roof, or correspondence, from an object xx to an object yy is a diagram of the form
s f↙ ↘ g x y \array{ && s \\ & {}^{f}\swarrow && \searrow^{g} \\ x &&&& y }
where ss is some other object of the category. (The word “correspondence” is also sometimes used for a profunctor.)
This diagram is also called a ‘span’ because it looks like a little bridge; ‘roof’ is similar. The term ‘correspondence’ is prevalent in geometry and related areas; it comes about because a correspondence is a generalisation of a binary relation.
Note that a span with f=1f = 1 is just a morphism from xx to yy, while a span with g=1g = 1 is a morphism from yy to xx. So, a span can be thought of as a generalization of a morphism in which there is no longer any asymmetry between source and target.
A span in the opposite category C opC^op is called a co-span in CC.
A span that has a cocone is called a coquadrable span.
Categories of spans
If the category CC has pullbacks, we can compose spans. Namely, given a span from xx to yy and a span from yy to zz:
s t f↙ ↘ g h↙ ↘ i x y z \array{ && s &&&& t \\ & {}^{f}\swarrow && \searrow^{g} & & {}^{h}\swarrow && \searrow^{i} \\ x &&&& y &&&& z }
we can take a pullback in the middle:
s× yt p s↙ ↘ p t s t f↙ ↘ g h↙ ↘ i x y z \array{ &&&& s \times_y t \\& && {}^{p_s}\swarrow && \searrow^{p_t} \\ && s &&&& t \\ & {}^{f}\swarrow && \searrow^{g} & & {}^{h}\swarrow && \searrow^{i} \\ x &&&& y &&&& z }
and obtain a span from xx to zz:
s× yt fp s↙ ↘ ip t x z \array{ && s \times_y t \\ & {}^{f p_s}\swarrow && \searrow^{i p_t} \\ x &&&& z }
This way of composing spans lets us define a bicategory Span(C)(C) with:
- objects of CC as objects
- spans as morphisms
- maps between spans as 2-morphisms
This is a weak 2-category: it has a nontrivial associator: composition of spans is not strictly associative, because pullbacks are defined only up to canonical isomorphism. A naturally defined strict 2-category which is equivalent to Span(C)Span(C) is the strict 2-category of linear polynomial functors between slice categories of CC.
(Note that we must choose a specific pullback when defining the composite of a pair of morphisms in Span(C)Span(C), if we want to obtain a bicategory as traditionally defined; this requires the axiom of choice. Otherwise we obtain a bicategory with ‘composites of morphisms defined only up to canonical iso-2-morphism’; such a structure can be modeled by an anabicategory or an opetopic bicategory?.)
We can also obtain a pseudo-double category?, whose loose structure is as above, whose tight morphisms are functions, and whose cells are commuting diagrams,
Moreover, when CC is an arbitrary category, not necessarily having pullbacks, one can still obtain a covirtual double category. More details can be found in Section 4 of Dawson, Paré, Pronk (where the term oplax double category is used).
Properties
The 1-category of spans
Let CC be a category with pullbacks and let Span 1(C):=(Span(C)) ∼1Span_1(C) := (Span(C))_{\sim 1} be the 1-category of objects of CC and isomorphism classes of spans between them as morphisms.
Then
- Span 1(C)Span_1(C) is a dagger category.
Next assume that CC is a cartesian monoidal category. Then clearly Span 1(C)Span_1(C) naturally becomes a monoidal category itself, but more: then
- Span 1(C)Span_1(C) is a dagger compact category.
Universal property of the bicategory of spans
We discuss the universal property that characterizes 2-categories of spans.
For CC be a category with pullbacks, write
-
Span 2(C)≔(Span(C)) ∼2Span_2(C) \coloneqq (Span(C))_{\sim2} for the weak 2-category of objects of CC, spans as morphisms, and maps between spans as 2-morphisms,
-
η C:C→Span 2(C)\eta_C: C \rightarrow Span_2(C) for the functor given by:
Now let
-
KK be any bicategory
-
F,G:C→KF, G \,\colon\, C \rightarrow K be functors such that every map in CC is sent to a map in KK possessing a right adjoint and satisfying the Beck-Chevalley Condition for any commutative square in KK,
-
α:F→G\alpha \,\colon\, F \rightarrow G be a natural transformation.
Then:
Proposition
(universal property of the bicategory of spans)
The following holds:
-
η C\eta_C is universal among such functors FF, i.e. FF as above factors as F=F^∘η CF = \hat{F} \circ \eta_C for a functor F^:Span 2(C)→K\hat{F} \,\colon\, Span_2(C) \rightarrow K which is unique up to isomorphism.
-
There exists a unique lax natural transformation: α^:F^→G^\hat{\alpha} \,\colon\, \hat{F} \rightarrow \hat{G} such that α^η C=α\hat{\alpha} \eta_C = \alpha.
-
Let x,yx, y be objects in CC and f:x→yf: x \rightarrow y be a morphism in CC. If (α x,α y)(\alpha_x, \alpha_y) induce a pseudo-map of adjoints F(f)⊣(Ff) *→G(f)⊣(Gf) *F(f) \dashv (Ff)^* \rightarrow G(f) \dashv (Gf)^*, then α^\hat{\alpha} is a pseudonatural transformation
Furthermore, if we denote PbkPbk as the 2-category of categories with pullbacks, pullback-preserving functors, and equifibered natural transformations and BiCatBiCat as the tricategory of bicategories, Span(−):Pbk→BiCatSpan(-): Pbk \rightarrow BiCat is well-defined as a functor.
Limits and colimits
Since a category of spans/correspondences Corr(𝒞)Corr(\mathcal{C}) is evidently equivalent to its opposite category, it follows that to the extent that limits exists they are also colimits and vice versa.
If the underlying category 𝒞\mathcal{C} is an extensive category, then the coproduct/product in Corr(𝒞)Corr(\mathcal{C}) is given by the disjoint union in 𝒞\mathcal{C}. (See also this MO discussion).
More generally, every van Kampen colimit in 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a (co)limit in Corr(𝒞)Corr(\mathcal{C}) — and conversely, this property characterizes van Kampen colimits. (Sobocinski-Heindel 11).
Relation to relations
Correspondences may be seen as generalizations of relations. A relation is a correspondence which is (-1)-truncated as a morphism into the cartesian product. See at relation and at Rel for more on this.
Examples
-
Spans in FinSet behave like the categorification of matrices with entries in the natural numbers: for X 1←N→X 2X_1 \leftarrow N \to X_2 a span of finite sets, the cardinality of the fiber X x 1,x 2X_{x_1, x_2} over any two elements x 1∈X 1x_1 \in X_1 and x 2∈X 2x_2 \in X_2 plays the role of the corresponding matrix entry. Under this identification composition of spans indeed corresponds to matrix multiplication. This implies that the category of spans of finite sets is equivalent to the Lawvere theory of commutative monoids, that is, to the PROP for the free bicommutative bialgebra. Spans over finite sets is a rig category with respect to the tensor products induced by the coproduct and product in FinSet. The coproduct in FinSet remains the coproduct, but the product becomes the bilinear tensor product of modules.
-
The Burnside category is essentially the category of correspondences in G-sets for GG a finite group.
-
A cobordism Σ\Sigma from Σ in\Sigma_{in} to Σ out\Sigma_{out} is an example of a cospan Σ in→Σ←Σ out\Sigma_{in} \to \Sigma \leftarrow \Sigma_{out} in the category of smooth manifolds. However, composition of cobordisms is not quite the pushout-composition of these cospans: to make the composition be a smooth manifold again some extra technical aspects must be added (“collars”).
-
In prequantum field theory (see there for details), spans of stacks model trajectories of fields.
-
The category of Chow motives has as morphisms equivalence classes of linear combinations of spans of smooth projective varieties.
-
The Weinstein symplectic category has as morphisms Lagrangian correspondences between symplectic manifolds.
More generally symplectic dual pairs are correspondences between Poisson manifolds.
-
Cospans of homomorphisms of C*-algebras represent morphisms in KK-theory (by Cuntz’ result).
-
Correspondences of flag manifolds play a role as twistor correspondences, see at Schubert calculus – Correspondences and at horocycle correspondence
-
The Fourier-Mukai transform is a pull-push operation through correspondences equipped with objects in a cocycle given by an object in a derived category of quasi-coherent sheaves.
-
A hypergraph is a span from a set of vertices to a set of (hyper)edges.
A category of correspondences is a refinement of a category Rel of relations. See there for more.
References
The terminology “span” appears on page 533 of:
- Nobuo Yoneda, On ext and exact sequences (PhD thesis), Journal of the Faculty of Science, Section I. 8 University of Tokyo (1960) 507–576 [pdf, CiNii:naid/500000325773]
The Span(C)Span(C) construction was introduced by Jean Bénabou (as an example of a bicategory) in
- Jean Bénabou, Introduction to Bicategories, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 47, Springer (1967), pp.1-77. (doi)
Bénabou cites an article by Yoneda (1954) for introducing the concept of span (in the category of categories).
An exposition discussing the role of spans in quantum theory:
The relationship between spans and bimodules is briefly discussed in
The relation to van Kampen colimits is discussed in
- Pawel Sobocinski, Tobias Heindel, Being Van Kampen is a universal property, (arXiv:1101.4594)
The universal property of categories of spans is due to
- Claudio Hermida, Representable Multicategories, Advances in Mathematics, 151 (2000), No. 2, 164-225, (doi:10.1006/aima.1999.1877)
and further discussed in:
-
R. Dawson, Robert Paré, Dorette Pronk, Universal properties of Span, Theory and Appl. of Categories 13, 2004, No. 4, 61-85, TAC, MR2005m:18002
-
R. Dawson, Robert Paré, Dorette Pronk, The span construction, Theory Appl. Categ. 24 (2010), No. 13, 302–377, TAC MR2720187
-
Charles Walker?, Universal properties of bicategories of polynomials, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 223.9 (2019): 3722-3777.
-
Charles Walker?, Bicategories of spans as generic bicategories, arXiv:2002.10334 (2020).
See also Theorem 5.2.1 and 5.3.7 of:
- Paul Balmer, and Ivo Dell’Ambrogio. Mackey 2-functors and Mackey 2-motives. arXiv:1808.04902 (2018).
The structure of a monoidal tricategory on spans in 2-categories is discussed in
- Alex Hoffnung, Spans in 2-Categories: A monoidal tricategory (arXiv:1112.0560)
Generally, an (∞,n)-category of spans is indicated in section 3.2 of
Last revised on December 4, 2024 at 15:51:33. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.