deductive system in nLab
Context
Deduction and Induction
Type theory
natural deduction metalanguage, practical foundations
type theory (dependent, intensional, observational type theory, homotopy type theory)
Foundations
The basis of it all
Set theory
- fundamentals of set theory
- material set theory
- presentations of set theory
- structuralism in set theory
- class-set theory
- constructive set theory
- algebraic set theory
Foundational axioms
-
basic constructions:
-
strong axioms
-
further
Removing axioms
Deductive systems
Definition
In logic, type theory, and the foundations of mathematics, a deductive system (or, sometimes, inference system) is specified by
- A collection of judgments, and
- A collection of steps, each of which has a (typically finite) list of judgments as hypotheses and a single judgment as conclusion. A step is usually written as
J 1⋯J nJ \frac{J_1 \quad \cdots \quad J_n}{J}
If n=0n=0, a step is often called an axiom. In set theory, if n>0n \gt 0, a step is usually called an axiom schema.
Usually, one generates the steps by using inference rules, which are schematic ways of describing collections of steps, generally involving metavariables.
Example
In the concrete algebraic theory of groups, the judgments are formal equations between terms built out of variables and the symbols ee, ⋅\cdot, and (−) −1(-)^{-1}. Thus, for instance, x⋅e=xx\cdot e = x and x=y⋅x −1x = y \cdot x^{-1} are judgments.
The rules of inference express, among other things, that equality is a congruence relative to the “operations”. For instance, there is a rule
a=a′b=b′a⋅b=a′⋅b′ \frac{a=a' \quad b=b'}{a\cdot b = a'\cdot b'}
where aa, bb, etc. are metavariables. Substituting particular terms for these metavariables produces a step which is an instance of this rule.
Proof trees and theorems
A proof tree in a deductive system is a rooted tree whose edges are labeled by judgments and whose nodes are labeled by steps. We usually draw these like so:
J 1J 2 J 3J 4 J 5 J 6 \array{\arrayopts{\rowlines{solid}} \array{\arrayopts{\rowlines{solid}} J_1 \quad J_2 \\ J_3} \quad \array{\arrayopts{\rowlines{solid}} J_4 \\ J_5} \\ J_6 }
(To draw such trees on the nLab, see the HowTo for a hack using the array
command. For LaTeX papers, there is the mathpartir package.)
If there is a proof tree with root JJ and no leaves (which means that every branch must terminate in an axiom), we say that JJ is a theorem and write
⊢J.\vdash J.
More generally, if there is a proof tree with root JJ and leaves J 1,…,J nJ_1,\dots, J_n, we write
J 1,…,J n⊢J. J_1, \dots, J_n \;\vdash\; J.
This is equivalent to saying that JJ is a theorem in the extended deductive system obtained by adding J 1,…,J nJ_1,\dots,J_n as axioms.
Formal systems
Depending on the strength of the metalanguage used to define the judgments and steps, simply having a deductive system does not in itself necessarily yield an effective procedure for enumerating valid proof trees and theorems. Deductive systems which do yield such an enumeration are sometimes referred to as formal systems. For example, Gödel’s incompleteness theorems are statements about formal systems in this sense. It is worth keeping in mind that more general deductive systems are considered in proof theory and type theory, typically because by side-stepping these coding issues one can give a simpler account of computational phenomena such as cut-elimination. A well-known example of such a so-called “semi-formal system” is first order arithmetic with the ω-rule?, used by Schütte in order to simplify Gentzen’s proof that the consistency of first-order arithmetic may be reduced to well-foundedness of the ordinal ϵ 0\epsilon_0.
Examples and special cases
Last revised on May 25, 2024 at 16:23:06. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.