over category (changes) in nLab
Showing changes from revision #51 to #52: Added | Removed | Changed
Context
Category theory
Contents
Definition
The slice category or over category C/c\mathbf{C}/c of a category C\mathbf{C} over an object c∈Cc \in \mathbf{C} has
-
objects that are all arrows f∈Cf \in \mathbf{C} such that cod(f)=ccod(f) = c, and
-
morphisms g:X→X′∈Cg: X \to X' \in \mathbf{C} from f:X→cf:X \to c to f′:X′→cf': X' \to c such that f′∘g=ff' \circ g = f.
C/c={X →g X′ f↘ ↙ f′ c} C/c = \left\lbrace \array{ X &&\stackrel{g}{\to}&& X' \\ & {}_f \searrow && \swarrow_{f'} \\ && c } \right\rbrace
The slice category is a special case of a comma category.
There is a forgetful functor U c:C/c→CU_c: \mathbf{C}/c \to \mathbf{C} which maps an object f:X→cf:X \to c to its domain XX and a morphism g:X→X′∈C/cg: X \to X' \in \mathbf{C}/c (from f:X→cf:X \to c to f′:X′→cf': X' \to c such that f′∘g=ff' \circ g = f) to the morphism g:X→X′g: X \to X'.
The dual notion is an under category.
Examples
-
If C=P\mathbf{C} = \mathbf{P} is a poset and p∈Pp \in \mathbf{P}, then the slice category P/p\mathbf{P}/p is the down set ↓(p)\downarrow (p) of elements q∈Pq \in \mathbf{P} with q≤pq \leq p.
-
If 11 is a terminal object in C\mathbf{C}, then C/1\mathbf{C}/1 is isomorphic to C\mathbf{C}.
-
For XX a topological space then the category of covering spaces over XX is a full subcategory of the slice category Top /XTop_{/X} of the category of topological spaces.
-
The fundamental theorem of topos theory states that the slice category over any object in a topos is itself a topos.
-
For a monoidal category the slice category over any monoid object is monoidal.
For instance, the slice topos of a given topos over any monoid object is canonically a monoidal topos (see the Example there).
Properties
Comonadicity
If CC admits binary coproducts with the fixed object cc, then the forgetful functor C/c→CC/c \to C is comonadic. See coreader comonad for more details.
Relation to codomain fibration
The assignment of overcategories C/cC/c to objects c∈Cc \in C extends to a functor
C/(−):C→Cat C/(-) : C \to Cat
Under the Grothendieck construction this functor corresponds to the codomain fibration
cod:[I,C]→C cod : [I,C] \to C
from the arrow category of CC. (Note that unless CC has pullbacks, this functor is not actually a fibration, though it is always an opfibration.)
Slicing of adjoint functors
\begin{proposition}\label{SliceAdjoints} (sliced adjoints) \linebreak Let
𝒟⊥⟶R⟵L𝒞 \mathcal{D} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;R\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;L\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\bot} \mathcal{C}
be a pair of adjoint functors (adjoint ∞-functors), where the category (∞-category) 𝒞\mathcal{C} has all pullbacks (homotopy pullbacks).
Then:
-
For every object b∈𝒞b \in \mathcal{C} there is induced a pair of adjoint functors between the slice categories (slice ∞-categories) of the form
(1)𝒟 /L(b)⊥⟶R /b⟵L /b𝒞 /b, \mathcal{D}_{/L(b)} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;R_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;L_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\bot} \mathcal{C}_{/b} \mathrlap{\,,}
where:
-
L /bL_{/b} is the evident induced functor (applying LL to the entire triangle diagrams in 𝒞\mathcal{C} which represent the morphisms in 𝒞 /b\mathcal{C}_{/b});
-
R /bR_{/b} is the composite
R /b:𝒟 /L(b)⟶R𝒞 /(R∘L(b))⟶(η b) *𝒞 /b R_{/b} \;\colon\; \mathcal{D}_{/{L(b)}} \overset{\;\;R\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/{(R \circ L(b))}} \overset{\;\;(\eta_{b})^*\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/b}
of
-
the evident functor induced by RR;
-
the (homotopy) pullback along the (L⊣R)(L \dashv R)-unit at bb (i.e. the base change along η b\eta_b).
-
-
-
For every object b∈𝒟b \in \mathcal{D} there is induced a pair of adjoint functors between the slice categories of the form
(2)𝒟 /b⊥⟶R /b⟵L /b𝒞 /R(b), \mathcal{D}_{/b} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;R_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;L_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\bot} \mathcal{C}_{/R(b)} \mathrlap{\,,}
where:
-
R /bR_{/b} is the evident induced functor (applying RR to the entire triangle diagrams in 𝒟\mathcal{D} which represent the morphisms in 𝒟 /b\mathcal{D}_{/b});
-
L /bL_{/b} is the composite
L /b:𝒟 /R(b)⟶L𝒞 /(L∘R(b))⟶(ϵ b) !𝒞 /b L_{/b} \;\colon\; \mathcal{D}_{/{R(b)}} \overset{\;\;L\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/{(L \circ R(b))}} \overset{\;\;(\epsilon_{b})_!\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/b}
of
-
the evident functor induced by LL;
-
the composition with the (L⊣R)(L \dashv R)-counit at bb (i.e. the left base change along ϵ b\epsilon_b).
-
-
\end{proposition} The first statement appears, in the generality of (∞,1)-category theory, as HTT, prop. 5.2.5.1. For discussion in model category theory see at sliced Quillen adjunctions. \begin{proof} (in 1-category theory)
Recall that (this Prop.) the hom-isomorphism that defines an adjunction of functors (this Def.) is equivalently given in terms of composition with
-
the adjunction unit η c:c→R∘L(c)\;\;\eta_c \colon c \xrightarrow{\;} R \circ L(c)
-
the adjunction counit ϵ d:L∘R(d)→d\;\;\epsilon_d \colon L \circ R(d) \xrightarrow{\;} d
as follows:
\begin{tikzcd} L(c) \ar[rr, f] && d &{\phantom{AAA}}\leftrightarrow{\phantom{AAA}}& c \ar[rr, \eta_c] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+12pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8.5pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && R \circ L(c) \ar[rr, R(f)] && R(d) \end{tikzcd}
\begin{tikzcd} c \ar[rr, \widetilde f] && R(d) &{\phantom{AAA}}\leftrightarrow{\phantom{AAA}}& L(c) \ar[rr, L(\widetilde{f})] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+8pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8.5pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && L \circ R(d) \ar[rr, \epsilon_d] && d \end{tikzcd}
Using this, consider the following transformations of morphisms in slice categories, for the first case:
(1a)
\begin{tikzcd} L(c) \ar[rr, f, dashed] \ar[dr] && d \ar[dl, p] \ & L(b) \end{tikzcd}
(2a)
\begin{tikzcd} c \ar[rr, {\eta_c}] \ar[dr] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+30pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+27pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && R \circ L(c) \ar[rr, {R(f)}, dashed] \ar[dr] && R(d) \ar[dl, R(p)] \ & b \ar[rr, \eta_b{below}] & & R \circ L(b) \end{tikzcd}
(2b)
\begin{tikzcd} c \ar[rr, dashed] \ar[dr] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+12pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && \eta_b^\ast\big(R(d)\big) \ar[rr] \ar[dl] \ar[dr, phantom, \mbox{\tiny\rmfamily(pb)}] && R(d) \ar[dl, R(p)] \ & b \ar[rr, \eta_b{below}] & & R \circ L(b) \end{tikzcd}
(1b)
\begin{tikzcd} L(c) \ar[dr] \ar[rrrr, L(\widetilde{f})] \ar[rrrrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+8pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && && L \circ R(d) \ar[rr, {\epsilon_d}] \ar[dl] && d \ar[dl, p] \ & L(b) \ar[rr, L(\eta_b){below}] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=-8pt\tikztostart.south) nodebelow{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=-8pt\tikztotarget.south) (\tikztotarget.south)}] & & L \circ R \circ L(b) \ar[rr, \epsilon_{L(b)}{below}] && L(b) \end{tikzcd}
Here:
-
(1a) and (1b) are equivalent expressions of the same morphism ff in 𝒟 /L(b)\mathcal{D}_{/L(b)}, by (at the top of the diagrams) the above expression of adjuncts between 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} and (at the bottom) by the triangle identity.
-
(2a) and (2b) are equivalent expression of the same morphism f˜\tilde f in 𝒞 /b\mathcal{C}_{/b}, by the universal property of the pullback.
Hence:
-
starting with a morphism as in (1a) and transforming it to (2)(2) and then to (1b) is the identity operation;
-
starting with a morphism as in (2b) and transforming it to (1) and then to (2a) is the identity operation.
In conclusion, the transformations (1) ↔\leftrightarrow (2) consitute a hom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the first claimed form (1).
\linebreak
The second case follows analogously, but a little more directly since no pullback is involved:
(1a)
\begin{tikzcd} c \ar[rr, dashed, f] \ar[dr] && R(d) \ar[dl] \ & R(b) \end{tikzcd}
(2)
\begin{tikzcd} L(c) \ar[rr, dashed, L(f)] \ar[dr] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+8pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && L \circ R(d) \ar[rr, \epsilon_d{above}] \ar[dl] && d \ar[dl] \ & L \circ R(b) \ar[rr, \epsilon_b{below}] && b \end{tikzcd}
(1b)
\begin{tikzcd} c \ar[rr, \eta_c{above}] \ar[dr] \ar[rrrrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=+12pt\tikztostart.north) nodeabove{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=+8pt\tikztotarget.north) (\tikztotarget.north)}] && R \circ L(c) \ar[rrrr,R(\widetilde{f})] \ar[dr] && %R \circ L \circ R(d) %\ar[rr, R(\epsilon_d){above}] %\ar[dl] && R(d) \ar[dl] \ & R(b) \ar[rr, \eta_{R(b)}{below}] \ar[rrrr, rounded corners, to path={ (yshift=-8pt\tikztostart.south) nodebelow{ \scalebox{} } (yshift=-8pt\tikztotarget.south) (\tikztotarget.south)}] && R \circ L \circ R(b) \ar[rr, R(\epsilon_b){below}] && R(b) \end{tikzcd}
In conclusion, the transformations (1) ↔\leftrightarrow (2) consitute a hom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the second claimed form (2). \end{proof}
\begin{remark} \label{LeftAdjointOfSlicedAdjunctionFormsAdjuncts} (left adjoint of sliced adjunction forms adjuncts) \linebreak The sliced adjunction (Prop. \ref{SliceAdjoints}) in the second form (2) is such that the sliced left adjoint sends slicing morphism τ\tau to their adjuncts τ˜\widetilde{\tau}, in that (again by this Prop.):
L /d(c ↓ τ R(b))=(L(c) ↓ τ˜ b)∈𝒟 /b L_{/d} \, \left( \array{ c \\ \big\downarrow {}^{\mathrlap{\tau}} \\ R(b) } \right) \;\; = \;\; \left( \array{ L(c) \\ \big\downarrow {}^{\mathrlap{\widetilde{\tau}}} \\ b } \right) \;\;\; \in \; \mathcal{D}_{/b}
\end{remark}
The two adjunctions in \ref{SliceAdjoints} admit the following joint generalisation, which is proven HTT, lem. 5.2.5.2. (Note that the statement there is even more general and here we only use the case where K=Δ 0K = \Delta^0.)
\begin{proposition}\label{SliceAdjointsGeneralized} (sliced adjoints) \linebreak Let
𝒞⊥⟵R⟶L𝒟 \mathcal{C} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;R\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;L\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\bot} \mathcal{D}
be a pair of adjoint ∞-functors, where the ∞-category 𝒞\mathcal{C} has all homotopy pullbacks. Suppose further we are given objects c∈𝒞c \in \mathcal{C} and d∈𝒟d \in \mathcal{D} together with a morphism α:c→R(d)\alpha: c \to R(d) and its adjunct β:L(c)→d\beta:L(c) \to d.
Then there is an induced a pair of adjoint ∞-functors between the slice ∞-categories of the form
(3)𝒞 /c⊥⟵R /b⟶L /b𝒟 /d, \mathcal{C}_{/c} \underoverset {\underset{\;\;\;\;R_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longleftarrow}} {\overset{\;\;\;\;L_{/b}\;\;\;\;}{\longrightarrow}} {\bot} \mathcal{D}_{/d} \mathrlap{\,,}
where:
-
L /cL_{/c} is the composite
L /c:𝒞 /c⟶L𝒟 /L(c)⟶β !𝒟 /d L_{/c} \;\colon\; \mathcal{C}_{/{c}} \overset{\;\;L\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{D}_{/{L(c)}} \overset{\;\;\beta_!\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{D}_{/d}
of
-
the evident functor induced by LL;
-
the composition with β:L(c)→d\beta:L(c) \to d (i.e. the left base change along β\beta).
-
-
R /dR_{/d} is the composite
R /d:𝒟 /d⟶R𝒞 /R(d)⟶(α *𝒞 /c R_{/d} \;\colon\; \mathcal{D}_{/{d}} \overset{\;\;R\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/{R(d)}} \overset{\;\;(\alpha^*\;\;}{\longrightarrow} \mathcal{C}_{/c}
of
-
the evident functor induced by RR;
-
the homotopy along α:c→R(d)\alpha:c \to R(d) (i.e. the base change along α\alpha).
-
\end{proposition}
Presheaves on over-categories and over-categories of presheaves
See slice of presheaves is presheaves on slice.
Let CC be a category, cc an object of CC and let C/cC/c be the over category of CC over cc. Write PSh(C/c)=[(C/c) op,Set]PSh(C/c) = [(C/c)^{op}, Set] for the category of presheaves on C/cC/c and write PSh(C)/Y(c)PSh(C)/Y(c) for the over category of presheaves on CC over the presheaf Y(c)Y(c), where Y:C→PSh(c)Y : C \to PSh(c) is the Yoneda embedding.
Proposition
There is an equivalence of categories
e:PSh(C/c)→≃PSh(C)/Y(c). e : PSh(C/c) \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} PSh(C)/Y(c) \,.
Proof
The functor ee takes F∈PSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) to the presheaf F′:d↦⊔ f∈C(d,c)F(f)F' : d \mapsto \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) which is equipped with the natural transformation η:F′→Y(c)\eta : F' \to Y(c) with component map η d:⊔ f∈C(d,c)F(f)→C(d,c)\eta_d: \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) \to C(d,c).
A weak inverse of ee is given by the functor
e¯:PSh(C)/Y(c)→PSh(C/c) \bar e : PSh(C)/Y(c) \to PSh(C/c)
which sends η:F′→Y(C)) \eta : F' \to Y(C)) to F∈PSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) given by
F:(f:d→c)↦F′(d)| c, F : (f : d \to c) \mapsto F'(d)|_c \,,
where F′(d)| cF'(d)|_c is the pullback
F′(d)| c → F′(d) ↓ ↓ η d pt →f C(d,c). \array{ F'(d)|_c &\to& F'(d) \\ \downarrow && \downarrow^{\eta_d} \\ pt &\stackrel{f}{\to}& C(d,c) } \,.
Example
Suppose the presheaf F∈PSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) does not actually depend on the morphisms to CC, i.e. suppose that it factors through the forgetful functor from the over category to CC:
F:(C/c) op→C op→Set. F : (C/c)^{op} \to C^{op} \to Set \,.
Then F′(d)=⊔ f∈C(d,c)F(f)=⊔ f∈C(d,c)F(d)≃C(d,c)×F(d) F'(d) = \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) = \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(d) \simeq C(d,c) \times F(d) and hence F′=Y(c)×FF ' = Y(c) \times F with respect to the closed monoidal structure on presheaves.
See also functors and comma categories.
For the analogous statement in (∞,1)-category theory see at (∞,1)-category of (∞,1)-presheaves -- Interaction with overcategories?.
Limits and colimits
Proposition
A colimit in an over category is computed as a colimit in the underlying category.
Precisely: let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a category, t∈𝒞t \in \mathcal{C} an object, and 𝒞/t\mathcal{C}/t the corresponding overcategory, and p:𝒞/t→𝒞p \colon \mathcal{C}/t \to \mathcal{C} the obvious projection.
Let F:D→𝒞/tF \colon D \to \mathcal{C}/t be any functor. Then, if it exists, the colimit of p∘Fp \circ F in 𝒞\mathcal{C} is the image under pp of the colimit over FF:
p(lim⟶F)≃lim⟶(p∘F) p \big( \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} F \big) \;\simeq\; \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} (p \circ F)
and lim⟶F\underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} F is uniquely characterized by lim⟶(p∘F)\underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} (p \circ F) this way.
This statement, and its proof, is the formal dual to the corresponding statement for undercategories, see there.
Proposition
For 𝒞\mathcal{C} a category, X:𝒟⟶𝒞X \;\colon\; \mathcal{D} \longrightarrow \mathcal{C} a diagram, 𝒞 /X\mathcal{C}_{/X} the comma category (the over-category if 𝒟\mathcal{D} is the point) and F:K→𝒞 /XF \;\colon\; K \to \mathcal{C}_{/X} a diagram in the comma category, then the limit lim←F\underset{\leftarrow}{\lim} F in 𝒞 /X\mathcal{C}_{/X} coincides with the limit lim←F/X\underset{\leftarrow}{\lim} F/X in 𝒞\mathcal{C}.
For a proof see at (∞,1)-limit here.
Initial and terminal objects
As a special case of the above discussion of limits and colimits in a slice 𝒞 /X\mathcal{C}_{/X} we obtain the following statement, which of course is also immediately checked explicitly.
Corollary
-
If 𝒞\mathcal{C} has an initial object ∅\emptyset, then 𝒞 /X\mathcal{C}_{/X} has an initial object, given by ⟨∅→X⟩\langle \emptyset \to X\rangle.
-
The terminal object of 𝒞 /X\mathcal{C}_{/X} is id X\mathrm{id}_X.
-
over-category
References
Formalization in cubical Agda:
Last revised on September 11, 2024 at 13:05:52. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.