rationalization in nLab
Context
Rational homotopy theory
and
rational homotopy theory (equivariant, stable, parametrized, equivariant & stable, parametrized & stable)
dg-Algebra
Rational spaces
PL de Rham complex
Sullivan models
Contents
- Idea
- Definition
- Rationalization of a homotopy type
- Rationalization as a localization of TopTop/∞Grpd\infty Grpd
- In homotopy type theory
- Properties
- Rationalization via PL de Rham theory
- Preservation of homotopy pullbacks
- Preservation of homotopy fibers
- Rationalization of spectra
- Related concepts
- References
Idea
In rational homotopy theory one considers topological spaces XX only up to maps that induce isomorphisms on rationalized homotopy groups π •(X)⊗ ℤℚ\pi_\bullet(X) \otimes_{\mathbb{Z}} \mathbb{Q} (as opposed to genuine weak homotopy equivalences, which are those maps that induce isomorphism on the genuine homotopy groups.)
Every simply connected space is in this sense equivalent to a rational space: this is its rationalization.
Similarly one may consider “real-ification” by considering π •(X)⊗ ℤℝ\pi_\bullet(X) \otimes_{\mathbb{Z}} \mathbb{R}, etc.
Definition
Rationalization of a homotopy type
We discuss here what it means for a map of homotopy types to exhibit the rationalization of its domain.
A widely appreciated construction applies in the special case that the domain is a simply connected homotopy type (in fact, more generally in the case that it is a nilpotent homotopy type). A slight enhancement of this construction, which is generally much less widely considered, applies to all connected homotopy types: this forms the rationalization of the universal cover (which is of course simply connected) but retains on this the information of the ∞ \infty -actions of the fundamental groups by deck transformations (see also at Borel-equivariant rational homotopy theory):
Rationalization of simply-connected spaces
A rationalization of a simply connected topological space XX is a continuous function ϕ:X→Y\phi \colon X \to Y, where
-
YY is a simply connected rational space;
-
ϕ\phi induces an isomorphism on rationalized homotopy groups:
π •(ϕ)⊗ℚ:π •(X)⊗ℚ⟶≃π •(Y)⊗ℚ \pi_\bullet(\phi)\otimes \mathbb{Q} \;\colon\; \pi_\bullet(X) \otimes \mathbb{Q} \stackrel{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} \pi_\bullet(Y) \otimes \mathbb{Q}
or equivalently if ϕ\phi induces an isomorphism on rational cohomology groups
H •(ϕ,ℚ):H •(X,ℚ)⟶≃H •(Y,ℚ). H^\bullet(\phi,\mathbb{Q}) \;\colon\; H^\bullet(X,\mathbb{Q}) \stackrel{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} H^\bullet(Y,\mathbb{Q}) \,.
or equivalently if ϕ\phi induces an isomorphism on rational homology groups
H •(ϕ,ℚ):H •(X,ℚ)⟶≃H •(Y,ℚ). H_\bullet(\phi,\mathbb{Q}) \;\colon\; H_\bullet(X,\mathbb{Q}) \stackrel{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} H_\bullet(Y,\mathbb{Q}) \,.
(Bousfield-Kan 72, p. 133-140, Bousfield-Gugenheim 76, 11.1, Hess 06, Def. 1.4 with Def. 1.7)
(notice here that ℤ\mathbb{Z} is a solid ring, in that ℚ⊗ ℤℚ≃ℚ\mathbb{Q} \otimes_{\mathbb{Z}} \mathbb{Q}\,\simeq\, \mathbb{Q}, e.g. here)
(Bousfield & Kan 1971, §3, Bousfield & Kan 1972, IV Prop. 4.1 (p. 109), see also Rivera, Wierstra & Zeinalian 2021, p. 7)
π 1\pi_1-Rationalization of connected spaces
For connected homotopy types XX which are not necessarily simply connected, consider their universal cover X^\widehat{X}, which sits in a homotopy fiber sequence
(1)X^ ⟶ X ↓ ↓ η X [−] 1 * ⟶ Bπ 1(X) \array{ \widehat{X} &\longrightarrow& X \\ \big\downarrow && \big\downarrow \mathrlap{ {}^{ \eta^{[-]_1}_X } } \\ \ast &\longrightarrow& B \pi_1(X) }
over the delooping/classifying space of the fundamental group (via the 1-truncation unit).
(Notice that this fiber sequence exhibits the ∞ \infty -action of π 1(X)\pi_1(X) on X^\widehat{X}.)
Here the universal cover X^\widehat{X} is simply connected (hence in particular nilpotent), so that the above notion of rationalization applies to this fiber:
Definition
(π 1\pi_1-rationalization)
A map η X ℚ:X⟶X ℚ\eta^{\mathbb{Q}}_X \;\colon\; X \longrightarrow X_{\mathbb{Q}} of connected homotopy types is called a π 1\pi_1-rationalization if
-
the higher homotopy group π n(X ℚ)\pi_n\big(X_{\mathbb{Q}}\big) are rational vector spaces;
-
η X ℚ\eta^{\mathbb{Q}}_X induces isomorphisms
-
on the fundamental groups
π 1(η X ℚ):π 1(X)→∼π 1(X ℚ) \pi_1\big(\eta^{\mathbb{Q}}_{X}\big) \;\colon\; \pi_1(X) \xrightarrow{\;\; \sim \;\;} \pi_1 \big( X_{\mathbb{Q}} \big)
-
on the the rationalization of all higher homotopy groups π n\pi_n for n≥2n \geq 2:
π n(η X ℚ)⊗ ℤℚ:π 1(X)⊗ ℤℚ→∼π 1(X ℚ). \pi_n\big(\eta^{\mathbb{Q}}_{X}\big) \otimes_{\mathbb{Z}} \mathbb{Q} \;\colon\; \pi_1(X) \otimes_{\mathbb{Z}} \mathbb{Q} \xrightarrow{\;\; \sim \;\;} \pi_1 \big( X_{\mathbb{Q}} \big) \,.
-
(Bousfield & Kan 1971, §3, p. 1008, see also Rivera, Wierstra & Zeinalian 2021, p. 8 and Ivanov 2021).
Rationalization as a localization of TopTop/∞Grpd\infty Grpd
In rational homotopy theory one considers the PL de Rham Quillen adjunction
(Ω •⊣K):dgAlg ℚ→K←Ω •sSet (\Omega^\bullet \dashv K) \;\colon\; dgAlg_{\mathbb{Q}} \stackrel{\overset{\Omega^\bullet}{\leftarrow}}{\underset{K}{\to}} sSet
between the model structure on dg-algebras and the standard model structure on simplicial sets, where Ω •\Omega^\bullet is forming Sullivan differential forms:
Ω •(X)=Hom sSet(X,Ω pl •(Δ Diff •)). \Omega^\bullet(X) = Hom_{sSet}(X, \Omega^\bullet_{pl}(\Delta^\bullet_{Diff})) \,.
The fundamental theorem of dg-algebraic rational homotopy theory says that on nilpotent spaces with finite type rational cohomology this induces an equivalence of homotopy categories.
Intrinsically this should model something like the (partially) left exact localization of an (∞,1)-category of ∞Grpd at those morphisms that are rational homotopy equivalences?.
∞Grpd ratio↪←∞Grpd. \infty Grpd_{ratio} \stackrel{\leftarrow}{\hookrightarrow} \infty Grpd \,.
Below we review classical results that says that the left adjoint (infinity,1)-functor here indeed preserves at least homotopy pullbacks.
More generally, a setup by Bertrand Toen serves to provide a more comprehensive description of this situtation: see rational homotopy theory in an (infinity,1)-topos.
In homotopy type theory
In homotopy type theory and synthetic homotopy theory, one considers the rationalization of a pointed 1-connected type.
Properties
Rationalization via PL de Rham theory
Proposition
(fundamental theorem of dg-algebraic rational homotopy theory)
Ho((DiffGradedCommAlgebras k ≥0) proj op)⊥⟶ℝexp⟵𝕃Ω PLdR •Ho(HoSimplicialSets Qu) Ho \left( \big( DiffGradedCommAlgebras^{\geq 0}_{k} \big)^{op}_{proj} \right) \underoverset { \underset {\;\;\; \mathbb{R} exp \;\;\;} {\longrightarrow} } { \overset {\;\;\; \mathbb{L} \Omega^\bullet_{PLdR}\;\;\;} {\longleftarrow} } {\bot} Ho \big( HoSimplicialSets_{Qu} \big)
of the Quillen adjunction between simplicial sets and connective dgc-algebras (whose left adjoint is the PL de Rham complex-functor) has the following properties:
-
on connected, nilpotent rationally finite homotopy types XX (2) the derived adjunction unit is rationalization
Ho(SimplicialSets Qu) ≥1,nil fin ℚ ⟶ Ho(SimplicialSets Qu) ≥1,nil ℚ,fin ℚ X ↦ ℝexp∘Ω PLdR •(X) \array{ Ho \big( SimplicialSets_{Qu} \big)^{fin_{\mathbb{Q}}}_{\geq 1, nil} & \overset{ }{\longrightarrow} & Ho \big( SimplicialSets_{Qu} \big)^{\mathbb{Q}, fin_{\mathbb{Q}}}_{\geq 1, nil} \\ X &\mapsto& \mathbb{R}\exp \circ \Omega^\bullet_{PLdR}(X) }
X⟶η X derrationalizationℝexp∘Ω PLdR •(X) X \underoverset {\eta_X^{der}} {rationalization} {\longrightarrow} \mathbb{R}\exp \circ \Omega^\bullet_{PLdR}(X)
-
on the full subcategories of nilpotent and finite rational homotopy types from Def. it restricts to an equivalence of categories:
Ho((DiffGradedCommAlgebras k ≥0) proj op) fin ≥1≃⟶ℝexp⟵𝕃Ω PLdR •Ho(HoSimplicialSets Qu) ≥1,nil ℚ,fin ℚ Ho \left( \big( DiffGradedCommAlgebras^{\geq 0}_{k} \big)^{op}_{proj} \right)^{\geq 1}_{fin} \underoverset { \underset {\;\;\; \mathbb{R} exp \;\;\;} {\longrightarrow} } { \overset {\;\;\; \mathbb{L} \Omega^\bullet_{PLdR}\;\;\;} {\longleftarrow} } {\simeq} Ho \big( HoSimplicialSets_{Qu} \big)^{\mathbb{Q}, fin_{\mathbb{Q}}}_{\geq 1, nil}
(Bousfield-Gugenheim 76, Theorems 9.4 & 11.2)
Preservation of homotopy pullbacks
Proof
This is effectively a restatement of a result that appears below proposition 15.8 in HalperinThomas and is reproduced in some repackaged form as theorem 2.2 of He06. We recall the model category-theoretic context that allows to rephrase this result in the above form.
Let C={a→c←b}C = \{a \to c \leftarrow b\} be the pullback diagram category.
The homotopy limit functor is the right derived functor ℝlim C\mathbb{R} lim_C for the Quillen adjunction (described in detail at homotopy Kan extension)
[C,sSet] inj⊥⟶lim C⟵constsSet. [C,sSet]_{inj} \underoverset {\underset{lim_C}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{const}{\longleftarrow}} {\;\;\; \bot \;\;\;} sSet \,.
At model structure on functors it is discussed that composition with the Quillen pair Ω •⊣K\Omega^\bullet \dashv K induces a Quillen adjunction
([C,Ω •]⊣[C,K]):[C,dgAlg op]⊥⟶[C,K]⟵[C,Ω •][C,sSet]. ([C,\Omega^\bullet] \dashv [C,K]) \;\colon\; [C, dgAlg^{op}] \underoverset {\underset{[C,K]}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{[C,\Omega^\bullet]}{\longleftarrow}} {\;\; \bot \;\;} [C,sSet] \,.
We need to show that for every fibrant and cofibrant pullback diagram F∈[C,sSet]F \in [C,sSet] there exists a weak equivalence
Ω •∘lim CF≃lim CΩ •(F)^, \Omega^\bullet \circ lim_C F \;\; \simeq \;\; lim_C \widehat{\Omega^\bullet(F)} \,,
here Ω •(F)^\widehat{\Omega^\bullet(F)} is a fibrant replacement of Ω •(F)\Omega^\bullet(F) in dgAlg opdgAlg^{op}.
Now, every object f∈[C,sSet] injf \in [C,sSet]_{inj} is cofibrant, and it is fibrant if all three objects F(a)F(a), F(b)F(b) and F(c)F(c) are fibrant and one of the two morphisms is a fibration. We may assume without restriction of generality that it is the morphism F(a)→F(c)F(a) \to F(c) that is a fibration. So we assume that F(a),F(b)F(a), F(b) and F(c)F(c) are three Kan complexes and that F(a)→F(b)F(a) \to F(b) is a Kan fibration. Then lim Clim_C sends FF to the ordinary pullback lim CF=F(a)× F(c)F(b)lim_C F = F(a) \times_{F(c)} F(b) in sSetsSet, and so the left hand side of the above equivalence is
Ω •(F(a)× F(c)F(b)). \Omega^\bullet(F(a) \times_{F(c)} F(b)) \,.
Recall that the Sullivan algebras are the cofibrant objects in dgAlgdgAlg, hence the fibrant objects of dgAlg opdgAlg^{op}. Therefore a fibrant replacement of Ω •(F)\Omega^\bullet(F) may be obtained by
-
first choosing a Sullivan model (∧ •V,d V)→≃Ω •(c)(\wedge^\bullet V, d_V) \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} \Omega^\bullet(c)
-
then choosing factorizations in dgAlgdgAlg of the composites of this with Ω •(F(c))→Ω •(F(a))\Omega^\bullet(F(c)) \to \Omega^\bullet(F(a)) and Ω •(F(c))→Ω •(F(b))\Omega^\bullet(F(c)) \to \Omega^\bullet(F(b)) into cofibrations follows by weak equivalences.
The result is a diagram
(∧ •U *,d U) ← (∧ •V *,d V) ↪ (∧ •W *,d W) ↓ ≃ ↓ ≃ ↓ ≃ Ω •(F(a)) ← Ω •(F(c)) → Ω •(F(b)) \array{ (\wedge^\bullet U^*, d_U) &\leftarrow& (\wedge^\bullet V^*, d_V) &\hookrightarrow& (\wedge^\bullet W^* , d_W) \\ \downarrow^{\simeq} && \downarrow^{\simeq} && \downarrow^{\simeq} \\ \Omega^\bullet(F(a)) &\stackrel{}{\leftarrow}& \Omega^\bullet(F(c)) &\stackrel{}{\to}& \Omega^\bullet(F(b)) }
that in dgAlg opdgAlg^{op} exhibits a fibrant replacement of Ω •(F)\Omega^\bullet(F). The limit over that in dgAlg opdgAlg^{op} is the colimit
(∧ •U *,d U)⊗ (∧ •V *,d V)(∧ •W *,d W) (\wedge^\bullet U^* , d_U) \otimes_{(\wedge^\bullet V^* , d_V)} (\wedge^\bullet W^* , d_W)
in dgAlgdgAlg. So the statement to be proven is that there exists a weak equivalence
(∧ •U *,d U)⊗ (∧ •V *,d V)(∧ •W *,d W)≃Ω •(F(a)× F(c)F(b)). (\wedge^\bullet U^* , d_U) \otimes_{(\wedge^\bullet V^* , d_V)} (\wedge^\bullet W^* , d_W) \simeq \Omega^\bullet(F(a) \times_{F(c)} F(b)) \,.
This is precisely the statement of that quoted result He, theorem 2.2.
check the following
Corollary
Rationalization preserves homotopy pullbacks of objects of finite type.
Proof
The theory of Sullivan models asserts that rationalization of a space XX (a simplicial set XX) is the derived unit of the derived adjunction (Ω •⊣K)(\Omega^\bullet \dashv K), namely that the rationalization is modeled by KK applied to a Sullivan model (∧ •V *,d)(\wedge^\bullet V^*, d) for Ω •(X)\Omega^\bullet(X).
X→KΩ •(X)←≃KΩ •(X)^:=K(∧ •V *,d V). X \to K \Omega^\bullet(X) \stackrel{\simeq}{\leftarrow} K \widehat {\Omega^\bullet(X)} := K (\wedge^\bullet V^* , d_V) \,.
Being a Quillen right adjoint, the right derived functor of KK of course preserves homotopy limits. Hence the composite K∘Ω •(−)^K \circ \widehat{\Omega^\bullet(-)} preserves homotopy pullbacks between objects of finite type.
Preservation of homotopy fibers
See at rational fibration lemma.
Rationalization of spectra
On spectra, rationalization is a smashing localization, given by smash product with the Eilenberg-MacLane spectrum HℚH \mathbb{Q}. (e.g. Bauer 11, example 1.7 (4)).
For more see at rational stable homotopy theory.
References
Classical accounts:
-
Aldridge Bousfield, Daniel Kan, Localization and completion in homotopy theory, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 77 6 (1971) 1006-1010 [doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1971-12837-9, pdf]
-
Aldridge Bousfield, Daniel Kan, p. 133-140 in: Homotopy Limits, Completions and Localizations, Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol. 304, Springer 1972 (doi:10.1007/978-3-540-38117-4)
-
Aldridge Bousfield, Victor Gugenheim, Def. 11.1 in: On PL deRham theory and rational homotopy type, Memoirs of the AMS, vol. 179 (1976) (ams:memo-8-179)
Review:
-
Kathryn Hess, Def. 1.7 in: Rational homotopy theory: a brief introduction, contribution to Summer School on Interactions between Homotopy Theory and Algebra, University of Chicago, July 26-August 6, 2004, Chicago (arXiv:math.AT/0604626), chapter in Luchezar Lavramov, Dan Christensen, William Dwyer, Michael Mandell, Brooke Shipley (eds.), Interactions between Homotopy Theory and Algebra, Contemporary Mathematics 436, AMS 2007 (doi:10.1090/conm/436)
-
Tilman Bauer, Bousfield localization and the Hasse square (2011) (pdf, pdf), chapter 6 in: Christopher Douglas, John Francis, André Henriques, Michael Hill (eds.), Topological Modular Forms, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs Volume 201, AMS 2014 (ISBN:978-1-4704-1884-7)
-
Tyler Lawson, Example 8.12 in: An introduction to Bousfield localization (arXiv:2002.03888) in: Andrew J. Blumberg, Teena Gerhardt, Michael A. Hill (eds.), Stable categories and structured ring spectra MSRI Book Series, Cambridge University Press
Review and further developments:
-
Manuel Rivera, Felix Wierstra, Mahmoud Zeinalian, Rational homotopy equivalences and singular chains, Algebr. Geom. Topol. 21 (2021) 1535-1552 [arXiv:1906.03655, doi:10.2140/agt.2021.21.1535]
-
Sergei O. Ivanov, An overview of rationalization theories of non-simply connected spaces and non-nilpotent groups [arXiv:2111.10694]
Last revised on July 16, 2022 at 21:59:42. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.